Law of value

Contents

General

The law of value is a central concept in Karl Marx's critique of political economy, first expounded in his polemic The Poverty of Philosophy (1847) against Pierre-Joseph Proudhon, with reference to David Ricardo's economics.[1] Most generally, it refers to a regulative principle of the economic exchange of the products of human work: the relative exchange-values of those products in trade, usually expressed by money-prices, are proportional to the average amounts of human labor-time which are currently socially necessary to produce them.[2] Thus, the exchange value of commodities (exchangeable products) is regulated by their value, where the magnitude of their value is determined by the average quantity of human labour which is currently socially necessary to produce them (see labor theory of value and value-form).

The "law of value" is often equated with the "labour theory of value" but this is strictly speaking an error. The law of value only states a general regulative principle about the necessary and inevitable relationship between the trading values of commodities, and the social labour-time currently required to make them. The labour theory of value in economics aims to explain how that determination actually works, what kinds of causal relationships are involved, how the law of value interacts with other economic laws, etc. For Marx himself, the "labour theory of value" referred only to the theory of value upheld by some of the classical political economists from William Petty to David Ricardo.

Marx never referred to his own theory as a "labour theory of value"; his own critique of the political economists was, that they all failed to explain satisfactorily how the determination of value by labour-time actually worked - they assumed it, but they did not explain it consistently (see below). Marx often regarded himself as perfecting a theory which had already existed for a long time, but which had never been consistently presented before. However, in the Marxist tradition, Marx's theory of value is conventionally labelled "the labour theory of value" - even although controversy still persists about how much Marx's theory actually differs from that of the classical political economists.[3] For some interpreters, Marx's theory departs very radically and absolutely from any "conventional" economics; for other interpreters, Marx's theory features both continuities and discontinuities with previous economic thought.

Gold referent

In Das Kapital Marx normally thinks of the quantity of labour that determines value as the ratio between the average total amount of labour-time required to produce a reproducible good, and the corresponding average amount of labour required to produce a unit of gold (see also gold standard).[4] His idea is effectively that the "value" of traded products is the objectified expression of the current social valuation of the human labour implicated in producing them.[5] How any individual happens to regard a particular product normally cannot change that social valuation at all; it's simply a "social fact" in the same way as "the state of the market" is a social fact, even though particular products can at any time trade at prices above or below their socially established value. Marx realized very well that the assumption of gold-money was a simplification - there might not be such a stable relationship between price-levels, average commodity values, and gold quantities - but he regarded the assumption as helpful in explaining the basic laws of motion of the capitalist mode of production. Adding in an extensive analysis of monetary and credit phenomena would only complicate the picture unnecessarily. The influence of the credit system on capitalist production is considered only in Capital, Volume III, part 5.

Formalization

While Marx used the concept of the law of value in his works Grundrisse, A contribution to the critique of political economy, Theories of Surplus Value and Das Kapital, he did not explicitly formalise its full meaning in a mathematical sense, and therefore how it should be exactly defined remains to some extent a controversial topic in Marxian economics. Different economists dispute about how the proportionality between exchange-value and labour-time should be mathematically understood or modelled, and about the measures which are relevant.[6] Underlying this debate are difficult conceptual questions about how the causal relationships in the economy between price relativities and time worked should be understood. Marx's analysis of value was "dialectical" in the sense that he thought value phenomena could only be understood dynamically, holistically and relationally, but he did not spell out all the conceptual, quantitative and logical implications of his position with great exactitude. The scholarly debate about those implications continues even today.[7]

Basic definition of the concept

Supply and demand

Excess demand can raise the exchange-values of products traded, and excess supply can lower them; but if supply and demand are relatively balanced, the question arises of what regulates the settled exchange-ratios (or average price-levels) of products traded in that case, and this is what the law of value is intended to explain. According to the law of value, the trading ratios of different types of products reflect a real cost structure of production, and this cost structure ultimately reduces to the socially average amounts of human labor-time currently required to produce different goods and services.

Cost structures and price structures

Simply put, if product A takes 100 hours of human work to produce in total, and product B takes 5 hours to produce, the normal trading-ratio of A and B will gravitate to a rate of around 1:20 (one of A is worth 20 of B), because A is worth much more than B. The trading ratio will never be 20:1, 1:5, 1:100, or 500:1 (unless there was an exceptional shortage or oversupply of these products, or unequal exchange took place). Moreover, if A and B are combined and used up to make product C in 40 hours, then product C is likely to be worth the equivalent of around 145 hours of human work in total (including the work of actually making product C).[8]

For that reason, most market trade in products is regular and largely predictable as far as price levels are concerned, rather than chaotic and arbitrary; norms of what products are worth relative to each other are mostly clearly known and established, even if people lack an exact knowledge of prices.

The concept of a "cost structure" refers here to the (direct and indirect) current labour inputs required to make a product, reflected in its price level. The concept of a "price structure" refers to the fact that prices rarely exist, or change, in isolation; instead, price-levels are interdependent on other price-levels, so that, if some prices would change, a lot of other prices would start to change as well - transmitting a change in valuation across the economy. Modern economics is indeed often viewed as a "science of prices", where economists make mathematical models of how particular prices can be affected by other prices. Marx argues that the cost structures and price structures for products are, in general, determined by the law of value. He was well aware of various "counteracting influences" but he evidently thought that such influences could not cancel out the law of value as a general law of motion (a determinant) of capitalist production.

Terms of exchange

The law of value originates in the "terms of exchange" established for different products. If a producer has to supply too much of his own product to get a different product, this has direct consequences for the additional time he has to work to sustain himself and the trading of his product. Yet the producer only has so much time, he doesn't have all the time in the world. In practical life, producers are rarely "stupid"; they know what the consequences are for their worktime if they trade on unfavourable terms; they know fairly accurately the maximum amount of product they are willing to trade to obtain another product, and they try to get the best return for their own product.[9]

Over time, and with more market integration, relatively stable values for products are established in accordance with production norms which exist independently of the productivity of individual producers. In that situation, each producer has to adapt his own production to those socially accepted values, the average terms of trade for products vary only within fairly narrow margins, and thus producers' activities fall under the sway of the law of value, which links "the economy of labour-time" with "the economy of trade".

In this way, Marx argues, production activities become dominated by the values of the products being produced and exchanged ("market forces"), often quite irrespective of what human needs might be, because these values determine whether it is "economic" or "uneconomic" to produce and trade products.

Field of application

The field of application of the law of value is limited to new output by producers of traded, reproducible labour-products[10], although it might indirectly influence trade in other goods or assets (for example, the value of a second-hand good may be related to a newly produced good of the same type). Thus, the law does not apply to all goods, services or assets in an economy, and it does not "rule" the whole economy, which contains far more assets and activities of all kinds (it "rules" only the working population, to the extent that their work effort is organized according to the principles of the commercial exchange of labour and its product).[11] Rather, it limits, regulates and constrains the trade in products.

Primary products are a special case, which Marx discusses in his theory of differential and absolute ground rent.[12] World market prices for primary products can at any time be strongly influenced by the yield of harvests and mines in different countries, regardless of labour effort.[13]

Origins of the concept

According to Marx, the knowledge that the law of value existed, expressed in one form or another, was very ancient. People knew very well that there was a definite relationship between time worked and the value of products traded; in itself that was not a very difficult insight to grasp.[14] The economic effects of the availability or lack of labour were rather self-evident in practical life. Nevertheless, different thinkers in history failed to conceptualize it with any adequacy.

In part, Marx believed that the reason was that unrestricted trade of almost everything (including all kinds of labour) purely according to their exchange-value, was a comparatively recent phenomenon in human history. In pre-capitalist societies, there were far more restrictions on trade, the scope of trade was much less, and trade was influenced much more strongly by local custom, religion and cultural tradition. It was therefore difficult for philosophers to reach the theoretical conclusion, that only human work effort is the real substance of economic value; it seemed to contradict all kinds of other influences at work.[15]

Adam Smith

The basic idea of the law of value was expressed very clearly by Adam Smith in The Wealth of Nations when he wrote:

"If among a nation of hunters, for example, it usually costs twice the labor to kill a beaver which it does to kill a deer, one beaver should naturally exchange for or be worth two deer. It is natural that what is usually the produce of two days' or two hours' labor, should be worth double of what is usually the produce of one day's or one hour's labor. If the one species of labor should be more severe than the other, some allowance will naturally be made for this superior hardship; and the produce of one hour's labor in the one way may frequently exchange for that of two hours' labor in the other..." .[16]

Utz-Peter Reich comments:

"This law of value is from Adam Smith (1776), the founding father of our economics science. As economists, however, we have been trained to reject this thesis, or more precisely to accept it only on the condition that the average cost equals the marginal cost of hunting those animals and this in turn equals the marginal utility of eating them. This value theory is firmly established in first-year economics."[17]

In this sense, neoclassical economist Paul A. Samuelson (1971) famously argued that "the beaver-deer exchange ratio can range anywhere from 4/3 to 2/1 depending upon whether tastes are strong for deer or for beaver" and, therefore, it seems that trading ratios are regulated only by the volume and intensity of consumer demand, as expressed by consumer preferences, rather than by labour-time.[18] According to the classical economists, however, such shifts in trading ratios would quickly cause a switch from beaver-hunting to deer-hunting or vice versa; short-term fluctuations in demand could not usually change the labour-costs of hunting as such, except if new technologies suddenly made it possible to capture more game in less labour-time, or if the herds of animals had become seriously depleted.[19] Thus Marx writes:

"Supply and demand regulate nothing but the temporary fluctuations of market prices. They will explain to you why the market price of a commodity rises above or sinks below its value, but they can never account for that value itself. Suppose supply and demand to equilibrate, or, as the economists call it, to cover each other. Why, the very moment these opposite forces become equal they paralyze each other, and cease to work in the one or the other direction. At the moment when supply and demand equilibrate each other, and therefore cease to act, the market price of a commodity coincides with its real value, with the standard price round which its market prices oscillate. In inquiring into the nature of that value, we have, therefore, nothing at all to do with the temporary effects on market prices of supply and demand."[20]

David Ricardo

The concept of the law of value was also stated by David Ricardo at the very beginning of his Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, as follows:

"The value of a commodity, or the quantity of any other commodity for which it will exchange, depends on the relative quantity of labour which is necessary for its production, and not on the greater or less compensation which is paid for that labour."[21]

At the most basic level, this Ricardian law of value specified "labor-content" as the substance and measure of economic value, and it suggests that trade will - other things being equal - evolve towards the exchange of equivalents (insofar as all trading partners try to "get their money's worth"). At the basis of the trading process is the economising of human time, and "normal" trading ratios become known to, or accepted, by economic actors. This leads naturally to the idea that the law of value will "balance out" the trading process.[22]

Karl Marx

Marx's real concern is to understand and analyze how the law of value determines or regulates exchange, i.e. how the balancing of the production of outputs and the demand for them could be accomplished, in a society based on a universal market such as capitalism, and how this was regulated by labour-time.[23] He tries to do this by starting off with simplifying assumptions and then gradually building up a complex theoretical structure.

Marx's theory specifically aims to grasp capital in motion, i.e. how, through the circulation and competitive dynamics of capital, changing expenditures of social labor are reconciled with (or fail to be reconciled with) changing social needs. This is an enormously complex undertaking, and Marx did not get much further than to specify the main tendencies and dynamics, and "pure cases". In the third volume of Das Kapital, he aims to show how the competition for profits from production is constrained by the law of value, and how this shapes the developmental pattern of capitalist production. He concludes that the law of value cannot directly regulate commodity prices in capitalist production, but only indirectly (prices of production are constrained by comparative costs in labour time).

Marx praised Adam Smith for already recognizing that in the transition "from simple commodity exchange and its law of value to... exchange between capital and wage-labour... something new occurs, [so that] apparently (and actually, in the result) the law of value changes into its opposite."[24]

However, Marx noted both Adam Smith and David Ricardo were unable to explain consistently how product-values were regulated by labour-time within capitalist production. They kept confusing capitalist exchange with simple exchange. Both Smith and Ricardo deeply believed that price structures for products were determined by the law of value; but, Marx argued, neither of them could explain how that value-price relationship operated, without contradicting themselves.[25] They could not theoretically reconcile the regulation of commodity trade by law of value, with profit-receipts in proportion to capital employed (rather than in proportion to labour-time worked).[26] Being at a loss at this point, Smith and Ricardo mooted the concept of "natural prices" instead, to postulate a "natural" (intrinsic) self-balancing tendency of markets - at the point where demand and supply were balanced, the "natural" price (the "true" value) had been reached.[27] The effect was that their "labour theory of value" was disconnected from their theory of capital distributions.

Economic value as such

Economic value exists necessarily, according to Marx, because human beings as social beings and moral subjects must co-operatively produce and economize their means of life to survive. Humans have to value things, and each other, in order to survive.

Relations of production

In so doing they are subject to relations of production. They know that their products have a socially accepted value, even if no trade occurs yet. Human valuations originate in the ability of living organisms to prioritize behaviours according to consciously self-chosen options, but social and individual valuations begin to interact. Three main kinds of relationships are involved which are objectively and empirically verifiable, and often formalised in law:

The attribution of value to labor-products, and therefore the economising of their use, occurs within these three types of relationships interacting with each other. The value of one product then depends on the value of many other products, and, in a community of independent private producers, their economic relations are then necessarily expressed through the product-values of what they trade. This expression involves character masks. Over time, most products acquire a normal exchange-value, meaning that what a product costs relative to other products remains fairly stable.

However, because these three types of relationships co-exist and interact objectively, as a given social fact, independently of particular individuals, it may appear that economic value is an intrinsic property of products, or alternately, that it is simply a characteristic that results from negotiations between market actors with different subjective preferences.

Marx recognised that value has both objective and subjective aspects - he tries to explain why economic value is perceived by people in a specific way[28] - but he was primarily concerned with the objectification of value through market trade, where objectified (reified) value relations rule human affairs (see value-form).[29] Paradoxically, he argues, this phenomenon meant that human lives became ruled and dominated by the products which people themselves had produced, and more specifically by the trading values of those products.

The mystery of economic value

When more and more of human requirements are marketised, and a complex division of labor develops, the link between value and labor-time becomes obscured or opaque, and economic value seems to exist only as an impersonal "market force" (a given structure of priced costs and sale-values) to which all people must adjust their behaviour. Human labor becomes dominated by the economic exchange of the products of that labor, and labor itself becomes a tradeable abstract value (see Abstract labour and concrete labour).

The result of the difficulties in explaining economic value and its sources is that value becomes something of a mystery, and that how the attribution of value really occurs is no longer clear.[30] The three relationships mentioned become mixed up, and are confused with each other, in commercial and economic discourse, and it appears that things and assets acquire an independent power to create value, even although value is a human attribution. Marx refers to this as commodity fetishism or thingification (Verdinglichung or reification) which culminates in what he calls fictitious capital. Value then seems to appear spontaneously out of trading activity. He regards this perception as an inevitable effect of commercial practice, since it involves the circumstance that objects acquire a value which exists independently of the valuer, a value "set by the state of the market" which individuals normally cannot change and must adjust to.

The end result is that value theory is banished from economics as a useless metaphysics, surviving only in the form of assumptions made about price behaviour (after all, we cannot talk about price aggregates without assuming some valuation principle or value criterion - we must be able to distinguish/define value equivalence and comparability, conserved value, value transfer, value used up or lost, value increase and value newly created). Because money-prices offer convenient quantifiable and generally applicable units of economic value, no further inquiry into value is deemed necessary.[31]

To solve the riddle of economic value, Marx argues, we must investigate the real historical origins of the conditions which give rise to the riddle in the first place, i.e. the real economic history of trade and the way that history has been reflected in human thought. Once we do this, value is no longer defined simply an attribute of products and assets, but as a relation between objects and subjects.[32]

Is it an equilibrium theory?

Some Marxists such as Thomas T. Sekine have interpreted Marx's law of value as a purely theoretical principle of market equilibrium which has no application to empirical reality.[33] This raises the question of how we verify that it is a "law" at all. Others such as Paul Mattick argued that Marx offered no theory of market equilibrium, only a dynamic theory of enlarged economic reproduction.[34] In reality, markets were rarely in equilibrium anyway (that was more a hypothesis used by economists, or a euphemism for "price stability"), and what explained the market behaviour of individuals and groups was precisely the imbalances between supply and demand propelling them into action. On this interpretation, capitalist development is always imbalanced development which, typically, the state tries to mitigate or compensate for.[35]

Market equilibrium and social stability

Under capitalist conditions, balancing output and market demand depended on capital accumulation occurring.[36] If profits were not made, production would stop sooner or later. A capitalist economy was therefore in "equilibrium" so long as it could reproduce its social relations of production, permitting profit-making and capital accumulation to occur, but this was compatible with all sorts of market fluctuations and disequilibria. So long as workers were "back to work" each working day, maintaining the value of assets and creating new value, it was "business as usual". Only when shortages or oversupply began to threaten the existence of the relations of production themselves, and block the accumulation of capital in critical areas (for example, an economic depression, a political revolt against capitalist property or against mass unemployment), a genuine "disequilibrium" occurred; all the rest was just ordinary market fluctuations. Marxist economist Paul Mattick comments:

"There can be no “equilibrium” between production and consumption, at any particular time or in the long-run, because progressive capital expansion means widening the gap between the two. Market “equilibrium” can exist only in abstract value terms: it exists when the market demand is one that will assure the realization of surplus-value by way of capital expansion. The semblance of a supply-and-demand “equilibrium” exists only within the process of capital accumulation. It is only in this sense that the law of value “maintains the social equilibrium of production in the turmoil of its accidental fluctuations.” Even so, in maintaining the “social equilibrium of production,” the law of value asserts itself just “as the law of gravity does when a house falls upon our ears.” It asserts itself by way of crises, which restore, not a lost balance between supply and demand in terms of production and consumption, but a temporarily lost but necessary “equilibrium” between the material production process and the value expansion process. It is not the market mechanism which explains an apparent “equilibrium” of supply and demand but the accumulation of capital which allows the market mechanism to appear, at times, as an equilibrium mechanism."[34]

So this kind of Marxian "equilibrium" was more a condition of social stability, not a hypothetical and unverifiable perfect match between supply and demand under idealised, static conditions. In any case, real social needs and their monetary expression through market demand might be two very different things. A demand might exist without any buying power, and it might be that more could technically be supplied, but isn't (see Capacity utilization). Economic equilibrium was not created by any perfect match of supply and demand, but by the social framework which permitted the balancing act to occur. The role of the political state was essential in this, to provide an enforced legal framework for fair trade, currency stability and secure property rights[37] Marx himself regarded the idea that society was somehow balanced out by market trade as a typical figment of bourgeois ideology and he was a strong critic of Jean-Baptiste Say. In the real world, there was only a more or less haphazard adjustment of supply and demand through incessant price fluctuations. In reality, a lot of non-market activity was necessary to keep market activity going,[38] and the role of the state was indispensable (for the security of private property, currency stability and the enforcement of trading obligations).[39]

The economic bicycle

The difference between the equilibrium theories of neoclassical economists and Marx's theory of the regulation of trade can be illustrated with a simple analogy. It is extraordinarily difficult to stay in balance while sitting on an ordinary bicycle, if the bicycle is stationary; but as soon as forward motion is achieved, balance is usually also achieved (give or take a few close shaves, perhaps). That balance therefore exists only as a motion involving the rider, the bike and the ground. All of these are necessary. If we just focused on the rider and the bicycle only, and ignored the ground, we would miss an important factor, to our peril.

A physicist would no doubt explain all this in terms of momentum, mass, velocity, kinetic energy, gyroscopic forces, torque and the law of gravity. The law of value performs a similar function in economic science. It tells us that the trading pattern in a society does not behave chaotically or arbitrarily, but is regulated at the very least by the relative proportions of work effort involved. A community of private producers working independently of each other has no other way to adjust their production volume to each other, than via the trading-value of their products. Exchange-value thus expresses a necessary relationship between the demand for a good by people who need it, and the quantity of society's labour-time required to produce it.

By contrast, what economists often concern themselves with is a question of this type: suppose the purpose of the bicycle is to be perfectly stationary, and the rider to sit on it while perfectly stationary. Under what conditions would the balancing act then be successful? What kind of bike would we need? What skills does the rider need? Which is interesting to speculate about. We could for example experiment with a unicycle, but most people do not ride unicycles and certainly not over long distances. A real economy has a "front wheel" (the economy of trade) and a "rear wheel" (the economy of labour-time). Because riding the bike we face forwards, we do not see the rear wheel, but that does not mean it isn't there. If it really isn't there, we can't ride.

While riding the bicycle, a potential risk exists that it will crash or collide with something; balance may be lost momentarily, yet also quickly restored. But the point is, we learn little about the possibilities or conditions for such an imbalance or crash from only examining the necessary conditions for a balancing act on a stationary bicycle - except trivia such as that if balance is not achieved, the rider must fall to the ground. We have to study the whole phenomenon interacting in motion.

More sophisticated econometric models in fact do this, by identifying the quantitative effects of the interaction of many different economic trends; this is sometimes referred to as "dynamic equilibrium", but it is often no longer clear what exactly is being equilibrated, or what the equilibrium would consist in (since in the last instance the knowledge of equilibrium depends on the observation that "things remain constant" according to some criterion). It is more a theory of how to prevent the decline or collapse of the circulation of commodities, money and capital, or promote balanced growth on some definition. The market equilibrium concept is also frequently confused with "the stability of the economic system".

15 factors counteracting the law of value

Just like the law of gravity, the law of value can interact with other phenomena which modify its effects.

A list

The 15 main factors counteracting the operation of the law of value, as a law governing the economic exchange of products, are:

All of these phenomena occur to some degree or other in any real economy. Hence the effect of the law of value would usually be mediated by them, and would manifest itself only as a tendency, or as a law of "grand averages".

Limits of price-value divergences

Nevertheless price-value divergences are typically quantitatively limited - whereas a fraction of goods and services will always trade for prices deviating significantly from what they are really worth, normally few people will buy an apple for $10 or sell a wellfunctioning car for $50 (unless it was part of some other deal). So although the real cost structure of production can be distorted by all kinds of extraneous factors, nevertheless the law of value places limits on the amount of the distortion. Even if goods sell at an abnormally low or high prices, that abnormality relates to a "normal" referent price, and it is precisely that price which, according to Marx, is constrained by the law of value, i.e. by the proportionalities of human labour-time.

There are many indications that Marx believed the future would see an increasingly "purified" capitalism. That is, obstructions to market expansion in every area would be cleared away through privatisation and removal of legal or technical restrictions on the expansion of trade, and that would in turn mean that the law of value would impose itself more, not less. Thus, the socially average real production costs would then influence the trading ratios in economic exchange more, not less; the allocation of goods would be determined more by private costs and private profits. Indeed, Marx felt confident about analyzing the commercial tendencies of capitalist development in their "purest form" precisely because he believed those tendencies would ultimately "win through" in the making of economic history, with "iron necessity". In other words, the "real" would in the long term increasingly approximate the theoretical "ideal", an ideal which abstracted from all kinds of contrary tendencies in local circumstances.[40]

Law of value in capitalism

Marx argues that, as economic exchange develops and markets expand while traditional methods of production are destroyed and replaced by commercial practices, the law of value is modified in its operation.

Production prices

Thus, the capitalist mode of production is a type of economy in which both inputs and outputs of production have become marketed goods and services (or commodities). In such an economy, Marx argues, what directly regulates the economic exchange of new labour-products is their prices of production. The production price is the price at which output would have to sell, in order to realize the average, normal rate of profit on the capital invested in producing that output. In pre-capitalist societies, where many inputs and outputs often weren't priced goods but allocated "by right" or according to custom, such an expression would be meaningless. The corollary in capitalist production is the free movement (or at least mobility) of labour and capital among branches of industry, in other words that capital and labour can be traded and shifted around fairly freely (in pre-capitalist societies, such market mobility was usually not possible).

Another way of saying the same thing, is that "sale at production prices becomes the normal precondition of supply" for new outputs produced[41] (although in particular cases, fluctuating market prices might be above or below the production price). This means two things: the average price for which a commodity sells will typically diverge to some extent from the labour-value it represents, so that more labour exchanges for less labour and vice versa, and that the exchange values realised in trade reflect not only a physical production cost, but also a "mark-up" or surplus-value in excess of that cost. Usually this is in a range of perhaps 8-15% of capital invested (net) or about 10-40% of product unit-prices in the market, depending on the case (there is obviously a difference between the profit rate on capital invested, and the profit rate obtained from selling a single commodity).

Price-value divergences

The fact that products can be traded above or below their value (and hence that more labour can exchange for less labour) became a fundamental theoretical problem for classical political economy. But for Marx, this was not an "aberration" in the exchange process at all, but instead the pivot of business competition in capitalist society. Price-value differences determined how much of the new surplus value produced by enterprises could be realized as profit.

Capitalist economic exchange, Marx argues (contrary to David Ricardo's theory), is not a simple exchange of equivalents.[42] It aims not to trade goods and services of equivalent value, but instead to make money from the trade (this is called capital accumulation). The aim is to "buy as cheaply as possible, and sell as dear as possible", under the competitive constraint that everybody has the same objective. The effect is that the whole cost-structure of production permanently includes profit as an additional impost - which, according to medieval Christian theologians, should never be more than one-sixth (16-17%) of the value of the traded object.[43] In an overall sense, Marx argues the substance of this impost is the unpaid surplus labour performed by the working class; part of society can live off the labour of others due to their ownership of property.[44]

In this situation, output values produced by enterprises will typically deviate from output prices realised. Market competition for a given demand will impose a ruling price-level for a type of output, but the different competing enterprises producing it will take more or less labour to produce it, depending on productivity levels and technologies they use. Consequently, output values produced by different enterprises (in terms of labour-time) and output prices realised by them will typically diverge (within certain limits): enterprises can get more or less income for the value of what they produce. That divergence becomes a critical factor in capitalist competition and the dynamics of the production system, under conditions where the average price-levels for products are beyond anyone's control.[45]

Competition between producers

If capital accumulation becomes the dominant motive for production, then producers will do everything they can to cut costs, increase sales and increase profits. Since they mostly lack control over the ruling market prices for their inputs and outputs, they try to increase productivity by every means at their disposal and maximise surplus labour. Because the lower the unit-costs of goods produced by an enterprise, the greater the margin will be between its own production costs and the ruling market prices for those goods, and the larger the profits that can be realised as result when goods are sold. Producers thus become very concerned with the value added in what they produce, which depends crucially on productivity. Marx comments:

"The fundamental law of capitalist competition, which political economy had not hitherto grasped, the law which regulates the general rate of profit and the so-called prices of production determined by it, rests... on [the] difference between the value and the cost-price of commodities, and on the resulting possibility of selling a commodity at a profit under its value."[46]

In the classical competitive situation, capitalists basically aim to employ workers to produce and sell a greater volume of products more quickly, at a competitive market-price which is below the socially established "normal" valuation for that kind of product which applies in market-trade, principally by means of a better labour-exploitation rate than their competitors, which lowers the cost-price per unit of product, yet provides a superior profit rate on capital invested, even if the selling price is below the normal valuation. Such price-cutting competition is limited in scope however, because if competitors adopt the same production methods, the productivity advantage will disappear. In addition, beyond a certain point workers will begin to resist their exploitation, and they may join trade unions. And, obviously, if market prices for products were reduced to their most competitive cost-prices only, profits would fall to zero; the commercial rationale for producing the products would then disappear altogether.

This leads to constant attempts worldwide to improve production techniques to cut costs, improve productivity and hold down labour-costs, but ultimately also to a decline in the labor-content of commodities. Therefore, their values will also decline over time; more and more commodities are produced, for a larger and larger market, at an increasingly cheaper cost. Marx claims that this trend happens "with the necessity of a natural law"; producers had no choice about doing what they could in the battle for productivity, if they wanted to maintain or increase sales and profits.[47] In business, if you don't go forward, you go backward. That was, in Marx's view, the "revolutionary" aspect of capitalism.[48]

However, competition inexorably gives rise to market monopolies, which may constrain further significant advances in productivity and innovation.[49] The negative influence of the tendency of the rate of profit to fall on business income can be overcome only by organizing production and sales on a larger and larger scale. To be able to compete in product markets in the end requires enormous amounts of investment capital, which (1) cuts out most would-be producers and (2) lowers the profit rate on investment capital. Investors will no longer commit very large amounts of capital to investment projects if they are uncertain about whether those projects will yield an adequate return in the future. The more uncertainty there is, the more difficult it is to "securitize" (insure) their longer-term investments against losses of capital. If the state will not provide financial backing, private finance must provide it, but the latter is reluctant to do so if the risks outweigh the yields. This causes a powerful development of capital markets and supporting financial services.

In a developed capitalism, the development or decline of the different branches of production occurs through the continual entry and exit of capital, basically guided by profitability criteria, and within the framework of competition. Where demand and profits are high, capital moves in, and when demand and profits are low, capital moves elsewhere. Thus, supply and demand are reconciled, however imperfectly, by the incessant movements of capital. Yet, Marx argues, this whole process is nevertheless still regulated by the law of value; ultimately, relative price movements for products are still determined by comparative expenditures of labour-time.[50] Thus, market prices for outputs will gravitate towards prices of production which themselves are constrained by product-values expressible in quantities of labour-time.[51]

Law of value and crises

In economic crises, Marx suggests, the structure of market prices is more or less suddenly readjusted to the evolving underlying structure of production values. Another way of saying this is, that the law of value will ultimately assert itself, by forcing a change in relative prices, in conformity with real production costs. In turn, this implies that although production values and market prices can diverge significantly from each other (in particular, because there exists no "perfect competition" - competition involves also blocking competitors), there are also limits to the possible discrepancies (because ultimately competitors will bring down artificially inflated prices, and goods sold further and further below value would eventually put producers out of business when incomes could no longer cover costs).

Smith's hidden hand

Neo-classical economics holds that, left to themselves, markets will balance supply and demand relatively quickly. If equilibrium does not exist, it will exist in the future, provided obstacles to market functioning are cleared away.

Al Greenspan's puzzle

In his Bundesbank speech on January 13, 2004, US Federal Reserve chairman Alan Greenspan, stated:

"Globalization has altered the economic frameworks of both developed and developing nations in ways that are difficult to fully comprehend. Nonetheless, the largely unregulated global markets do clear, and, with rare exceptions, appear to move effortlessly from one state of equilibrium to another. It is as though an international version of Adam Smith's "invisible hand" is at work."[52]

This was a reference to Adam Smith's Wealth of Nations (1776) where Smith wrote:

"Every individual intends only his own gain, and he is in this, as in many other cases, led by an invisible hand to promote an end which was no part of his original intention. By pursuing his own interest he frequently promotes that of society more effectively than when he really intends to promote it."[53]

Marx's theory of how the law of value operates in capitalism aims to reveal what the "hidden hand" of markets theorised by Adam Smith really consists of.[54] It aims to explain how it comes about, that the markets get "a life of their own", by showing what drives the markets, and how the market-balancing process actually occurs.[55] But it can do so only by distinguishing between a domain of value-relations and a domain of price-relations, and between potential values and actual prices realised; after all, a process is involved whereby products move into markets, are sold for a price, and then move out of markets or are resold; this can be rationally understood only by assuming a temporal continuity (or conservation) of product-values through successive exchanges.[56]

George Soros and the reflexivity of economic value

Another "take" on the law of value, from an investor's perspective, is by George Soros:[57]

"Every market participant is faced with the task to estimate the value in the present of a future development of events, but that development is co-determined by the value which all market participants together attribute to it in the present. That is why market participants are forced to be led partly by their subjective judgement. Characteristic of that bias is that it is not purely passive: it has influence on the course of events which it should represent. This active aspect is lacking in the concept of equilibrium such as is used in economic theory."[58]

In the real world, investors are constantly juggling between actual market prices and hypothetical (ideal) prices, based on assumptions about what the objective value of a good (its "real worth") is likely to be, now and in the future. A difficulty here is that the majority of objects of value in a society at any time don't have any actual market price, because they are not being traded. Thus, value proportions between those objects objectively exist, but at best these can only be approximated or estimated in price terms.

The economist gets on his bike

Marx tries to model the market outcomes macro-economically with regard to new outputs from production, assuming that values and prices will diverge, the argument being that this divergence will create a systematic pattern of economic behaviour by producers and investors. He is not interested in the circus-act of a clown balancing on a stationary bicycle, but in the bicycle ride. Once the economist is riding on his bike, he can discover many things that he would never know about, if he just tried balancing on it while it is stationary, or just theorizes about that possibility.

Modification of the law of value in the world market

Marx believed that the operation of the law of value was not only modified by the capitalist mode of production, but also in the world market (world trade, as contrasted with the home market or national economy).[59]

Productivity differentials

The main reason for this was the existence of different levels of the intensity and productivity of labour in different countries, creating for example a very different cost structure in different countries for all kinds of products.[60] Products that took 1 hour of labour to make in country A might take 10 hours to make in country B, a difference in production costs which could strongly influence the exchange values realised in the trade between A and B. More labour could, in effect, exchange for less labour (an "unequal exchange" in value terms) for a prolonged time. In addition, the normal rate of surplus value could be different in different countries - one hour of labour might cost $1 in country A, $10 in country B, and $20 in country C. That makes a huge difference not only to profitability, but to the ability to sell products at competitive prices.

So traders would try to use this differential to their advantage, with the usual motto "buy cheap, sell dear". The result, some Marxists argue, is an international transfer of value, from countries with a weaker bargaining position to those with a stronger one: products produced in country A with undervalued labour are acquired for a low price and resold in country B where labour is more highly valued, for a much higher price.[61] The differential in labour valuations becomes a source of profit (see also global labor arbitrage).

German debate

Among German Marxists, Marx's fragmentary remarks on the law of value in a world market setting stimulated an important theoretical debate in the 1970s and early 1980s.[62] One aim of this debate was to move beyond crude Ricardian interpretations of comparative advantage or comparative costs in explaining the pattern of world trade. To some extent similar debates took place in the USA, France and Japan.[63]

In particular, when the volume of intra-industry trade (IIT) between countries grows (i.e. the same kinds of products are both imported and exported by a country, e.g. cars, wine, beer, clothes, vegetables), and when different branches of the same multinational import and export between countries with their own internal price regime, international comparative advantage theories of the Ricardian type do not apply.

Nowadays, Marxian scholars argue, comparative advantage survives mainly as an ideology justifying the benefits of international trade, not as an accurate description of that trade (some economists however draw subtle distinctions between comparative "advantages" and comparative "costs", while others switch to the concept of competitive advantage).[64]

Ultimately, the "comparative advantage" ideology is based on a very simple ideology about trade. This ideology says, that if everybody specializes in what they are the best at producing, this provides the greatest amount of wealth for everybody, because then everybody will be operating in the most efficient way. But this ideology is hopelessly naive. The simple reason is that, even if products are produced very efficiently, this says nothing about the terms on which products will be traded, and the incomes which producers will get for their work. They might work very efficiently, but get very little money for their effort.

Uneven development

The operation of the law of value in the world market might however seem rather abstract, in view of the phenomena of unequal exchange, differences in accounting norms, protectionism, debt-driven capital accumulation and gigantic differences in currency exchange rates between rich and poor countries. These phenomena can create very a significant distortion in world trade between final market prices for goods, and the real production costs for those goods, resulting in superprofit for the beneficiaries of the trade.

Jayati Ghosh writes:

"While developing countries as a group more than doubled their share of world manufacturing exports from 10.6 per cent in 1980 to 26.5 per cent in 1998, their share of manufacturing value added increased by less than half, from 16.6 per cent to 23.8 per cent. By contrast, developed countries experienced a substantial decline in share of world manufacturing exports, from 82.3 per cent to 70.9 per cent. But at the same time their share of world manufacturing value added actually increased, from 64.5 per cent to 73.3 per cent."[65]

That is, the value and physical volume of manufactured exports by developing countries increased gigantically more than the actual income obtained by the producers. Third world exporters might have got mighty rich, but the reality is that third world nations relatively speaking received less and less for what they produced for sale in the world market, even as they produced more and more; this is also reflected in the international terms of trade for manufactured products.

Global production prices

The postulate of the law of value does however lead to the Marxian historical prediction that global prices of production will be formed by world competition among producers in the long term. That is, the conditions for producing and selling products in different countries will be equalised in the long run through global market integration; this will be reflected also in International Financial Reporting Standards. Thus globalisation means that incipiently the "levelling out of differences in rates of profit" through competition begins to operate internationally.[66] Trading ratios and exchange-values for products sold globally would thus become more and more similar, in the long term.[67]

Hamburger example

This hypothesis can be empirically tested by means of international price comparisons. To illustrate (this is only an approximate, simplified calculation) according to the Big Mac Index of The Economist, on July 22, 2010 the average cost of a big mac hamburger was highest ($7.38) in Norway and lowest ($1.81) in the Ukraine. Nominally, the Norwegian burger therefore costs four times the Ukrainian one, if one works with a US dollar valuation. When, however, one adjusts for purchasing power parity, the Norwegian burger is worth about $4.93 and the Ukrainian burger is worth about $5.25. In other words, Norwegians have a higher wage, but they can buy less for their money. VAT on the Norwegian burger is 14% and VAT on the Ukrainian burger is 20% so the Norwegian burger before indirect tax imposts costs $4.24 and the Ukrainian one $4.20.

Admittedly, corporate tax in Norway is at 28%, and it is 25% in the Ukraine, so one could in principle weight these results most simply by reducing the Norwegian cost by 3% to get a more accurate picture of the difference in direct production cost. To express the real disparity in value, we could then strike a ratio between $4.11 (for the Norwegian burger) and $4.20 (for the Ukrainian burger), i.e. the real differential in value between the nominally most expensive burger in the world and the nominally least expensive burger in the world, expressed in US dollars, is likely to be around 2%.

In the rest of the world, one could conclude, for the most part international value differentials for burgers are unlikely to be very much larger (in fact, the tax and social security levies involved in the total labour cost of a MacDonald's employee are proportionally somewhat higher in the Ukraine than in Norway).

Crucial quotations

Marx on the law of value

In his letter to Louis Kugelmann of July 11, 1868, Karl Marx commented gruffly:

"As for the Centralblatt, the man is making the greatest concession possible by admitting that, if value means anything at all, then my conclusions must be conceded. The unfortunate fellow does not see that, even if there were no chapter on 'value' at all in my book, the analysis I give of the real relations would contain the proof and demonstration of the real value relation. The chatter about the need to prove the concept of value arises only from complete ignorance both of the subject under discussion and of the method of science. Every child knows that any nation that stopped working, not for a year, but let us say, just for a few weeks, would perish. And every child knows, too, that the amounts of products corresponding to the differing amounts of needs demand differing and quantitatively determined amounts of society's aggregate labour. It is self-evident that this necessity of the distribution of social labour in specific proportions is certainly not abolished by the specific form of social production; it can only change its form of manifestation. Natural laws cannot be abolished at all. The only thing that can change, under historically differing conditions, is the form in which those laws assert themselves. And the form in which this proportional distribution of labour asserts itself in a state of society in which the interconnection of social labour expresses itself as the private exchange of the individual products of labour, is precisely the exchange value of these products. Where science comes in is to show how the law of value asserts itself. So, if one wanted to 'explain' from the outset all phenomena that apparently contradict the law, one would have to provide the science before the science. It is precisely Ricardo's mistake that in his first chapter, on value, all sorts of categories that still have to be arrived at are assumed as given, in order to prove their harmony with the law of value. On the other hand, as you correctly believe, the history of the theory of course demonstrates that the understanding of the value relation has always been the same, clearer or less clear, hedged with illusions or scientifically more precise. Since the reasoning process itself arises from the existing conditions and is itself a natural process, really comprehending thinking can always only be the same, and can vary only gradually, in accordance with the maturity of development, hence also the maturity of the organ that does the thinking. (...) The vulgar economist has not the slightest idea that the actual, everyday exchange relations and the value magnitudes cannot be directly identical. The point of bourgeois society is precisely that, a priori, no conscious social regulation of production takes place. What is reasonable and necessary by nature asserts itself only as a blindly operating average. The vulgar economist thinks he has made a great discovery when, faced with the disclosure of the intrinsic interconnection, he insists that things look different in appearance. In fact, he prides himself in his clinging to appearances and believing them to be the ultimate. Why then have science at all? But there is also something else behind it. Once interconnection has been revealed, all theoretical belief in the perpetual necessity of the existing conditions collapses, even before the collapse takes place in practice. Here, therefore, it is completely in the interests of the ruling classes to perpetuate the unthinking confusion. And for what other reason are the sycophantic babblers paid who have no other scientific trump to play except that, in political economy, one may not think at all!"[68]

Frederick Engels on the law of value

"...the Marxian law of value holds generally, as far as economic laws are valid at all, for the whole period of simple commodity production — that is, up to the time when the latter suffers a modification through the appearance of the capitalist form of production. Up to that time, prices gravitate towards the values fixed according to the Marxian law and oscillate around those values, so that the more fully simple commodity production develops, the more the average prices over long periods uninterrupted by external violent disturbances coincide with values within a negligible margin. Thus, the Marxian law of value has general economic validity for a period lasting from the beginning of exchange, which transforms products into commodities, down to the 15th century of the present era. But the exchange of commodities dates from a time before all written history — which in Egypt goes back to at least 2500 B.C., and perhaps 5000 B.C., and in Babylon to 4000 B.C., perhaps to 6000 B.C.; thus, the law of value has prevailed during a period of from five to seven thousand years."[69]

Engels apparently believed that the law of value directly regulated the simple exchange of products up to the 15th century, whereupon simple exchange began to give way to capitalist exchange of products regulated by the prices of production. This did not mean that Engels believed "a society consisting exclusively of simple commodity producers" had ever existed. It meant just that commodity trade was very ancient, emerging at first - as Marx noted - in the interstices of traditional agrarian societies, as an ancillary economic activity. For most of the history of civil society, commodity trade did not dominate the economy. Marx's whole point was that as soon as "generalized commodity production" emerged (where both the inputs and the outputs of production are all commodities), production became fully subordinated to the laws of capital accumulation. But for most of human history, "generalized" commodity production never existed; for most of human history, commercial production was at best only a specific branch of production, not most of production. Of course, even in a developed capitalist economy, plenty of non-commercial production also occurs, e.g. household production, or production by the state authorities. Nevertheless such non-commercial production is often valued or evaluated according to what it is worth in money terms (or how much money it saves).

The law of value in non-capitalist societies

There has been a long and drawn-out debate among Marxists about whether the law of value also operates in non-capitalist societies where production is directed mainly by the state authorities. There is still little agreement on the issue, because different Marxists use different definitions and concepts which are often influenced by political attitudes (for example, some regarded the Soviet Union as "socialist", others as "capitalist", and still others as "neither capitalist nor socialist").

Joseph Stalin

In his famous pamphlet Economic Problems of Socialism in the USSR, Joseph Stalin argued that the law of value did operate in the socialist economy of the USSR.[70] After all, Marx had stated in Das Kapital that:

"...after the abolition of the capitalist mode of production, but still retaining social production, the determination of value continues to prevail in the sense that the regulation of labour-time and the distribution of social labour among the various production groups, ultimately the book-keeping encompassing all this, become more essential than ever."[71]

Stalin was primarily concerned at the time with the problem of wasted labour, in an economy where workers often could not be easily fired (they had a constitutionally guaranteed right to a job, and there was considerable featherbedding of employees), and where there was often no clear relationship between salary-levels, work performance and actual output. The Stalin theory of the law of value was critically discussed by Włodzimierz Brus in The market in a socialist economy.[72]

Supporters of the theory of state capitalism in the USSR and scholars such as Andre Gunder Frank have also believed that the law of value operated in Soviet-type societies.[73] However, it is not always clear what they mean by the law of value, beyond the vague idea that the direct producers remain dominated by their own products, or that labour costs remain important, or that Soviet-type societies remained influenced by the world market.

Ernest Mandel

According to Ernest Mandel, the law of value, as a law of exchange, did influence non-capitalist societies to some extent, inasmuch as exchange and trade persisted, but because the state directed the bulk of economic resources, the law of value no longer ruled or dominated resource allocation.[74] The best proof of that was, that there was mostly no clear relationship at all anymore between the exchange-value of goods traded, and what it really cost to produce them; accounting information, insofar as it was valid, might in fact be unable to show anything about the real nature of resource allocation. Insofar as the social priorities of state policy ensured that people got what they needed, that was a good thing; but insofar as resources were wasted because of a lack of sensible cost-economies, it was a bad thing. Cost-accounting is, of course, no more "neutral" than profit-accounting; a lot depends on what costs are included and excluded in the calculation.

Che Guevara

Che Guevara adopted a similar view in socialist Cuba; if more resources were directly allocated to satisfy human needs, instead of commercially supplied, a better life for people would result. Guevara organised an interesting conference at which the theoretical issues were debated[75] Generally, the New Left adopted the idea that true socialism would involve the abolition of the law of value, since commodity production would be abolished - goods and services would be allocated according to need, and primarily according to non-market principles. But even if this claim is accepted, it still remains true that people cannot get away from the physical reality that the products they consume inescapably take a certain quantity of work effort to produce. In that sense, as Marx implies, there is still a "law of labour" to be reckoned with, i.e. the necessity to allocate, account for, and economize work effort so that people can get the products they need to live. Guevara proposed a mix of moral and material incentives to ensure this would be the case.

John Weeks

Some Marxist authors, such as John Weeks, have argued that the law of value is unique to an economy based on the capitalist mode of production.[76] They reject the claim by Engels that the law of value is associated with the entire history of economic exchange (trade), and modified when the vast majority of inputs and outputs of production have become marketed, priced commodities. Marx himself said that the law of value "develops fully only on the foundation of capitalist production", implying that the law of value already asserted itself before capitalist production.[77]

Other Marxists (including Ernest Mandel and the Japanese scholar Kozo Uno) followed Marx & Engels in believing that the law of value emerges and develops from simple exchange.[78] Here, it is argued that, if the law of value was unique to capitalism, it becomes impossible to explain the development of pre-capitalist commodity exchange or the evolution of trading processes in a way consistent with historical materialism and Marx's theory of value. So a better approach, it is argued, is to regard the application of the law of value as being modified in the course of the expansion of trade and markets, including more and more of production in the circuit of capital. In that case, a specific society must be investigated to discover the regulating role that the law of value plays in economic exchange.

Heinz Dieterich's equivalence economy

In contemporary Venezuela, the German socialist economist Heinz Dieterich has argued that the production and distribution of products should occur in accordance with their true labour costs, as shown by special macro-economic labour accounts estimating how much work-time products take to make (in Socialism of the 21st century this is called "equivalence economy").

However, this argument is very controversial. Its critics claim it is practically impossible, and some indeed point to Marx's rejection in the Grundrisse of the "time-chit" theory of allocating goods proposed by 18th and 19th century utopian socialists such as John Francis Bray and John Gray[79] On this view, Dieterich at most shows that the allocation of goods according to commercial principles is only one method of allocating resources; other methods such as sharing, redistribution, subsidization, barter, grants and direct allocation according to need may often serve the interest of fairness, efficiency and social justice better, provided that people accept a common ethic about what is best for all, if they can see that adopting such an ethic has good results.

In almost any society, market and non-market methods of allocating resources are in practice combined, which is acknowledged in official national accounts by the inclusion of market and non-market sectors. The real question for economists is how the two can be combined to achieve the best economic result for citizens, and what the effect is of market and non-market methods on each other.[80] This can be a highly politicized and contentious dispute, since the chosen methods can advantage some and disadvantage others; it is very difficult to devise allocation methods which distribute the gains and losses of economic policy in an equal or equitable way among all economic actors.

Criticism

Traditionally, criticism of Marx's law of value has been of three kinds: conceptual, logical, and empirical.

Conceptual criticism

The conceptual criticism concerns the concept of value itself.

Objective/subjective

For Marx, economic value in capitalist society was an objectified social characteristic of labour-products, exchanged in an economic community, given the physical reality that products took a definite amount of society's labour-time to produce, for a given demand. A product had a value, regardless of what any particular person might think about it, priced or unpriced (see value-form). Marx regarded the law of value as analogous to an objective physical law, since people could never escape from the fact that the products they consumed presupposed an objective cost in human labour time. Critics however argue that economic value is something purely subjective, i.e. a personal valuation determined by personal preferences and marginal utility; only prices are objective.[81] One of the first Marx-critics to argue this was the Austrian Eugen von Bohm-Bawerk.[82]

However, many prices are not objective either - they are only ideal prices used for the purpose of calculation, accounting and estimation, not actually charged or applying directly to any real transaction.[83] Yet, these notional prices can nevertheless influence economic behaviour, inasmuch as the prices estimated affect expectations of incomes and expenditures. Economists then debate about when a price can be said to be "objective". Objectivity of prices, could be taken to mean e.g. only that the prices are empirically observable, not that they are independent from subjective values. But many prices are not empirically observable either, they exist only as a numerical idea. For that reason, markets become very mysterious things: does the price-level change, because of a subjective preference, or does subjective preference change, because of the price-level? The point is that we can never know the answer for sure; at best we can "model" the most likely interactions between preferences and prices.

Cost structures and price structures

In almost all cases, cars will sell for more than carrots, but why? If value is subjective, all we can say is that people value cars more than carrots, or that cars are more in demand than carrots. Marx argues by contrast that cars and carrots have different objective costs of production, reducible to different amounts of labour-time. So cars will always cost more than carrots; one car will trade for, or be worth, quite a few tonnes of carrots, at least in the normal situation.

Against this view, one could also argue that objective amounts of comparable resources (such as energy, land, water, etc.), necessary to manufacture a car, are much larger than resources necessary for growing a carrot, explaining why the cost (and, hence, minimal price) of a car is larger than the cost of a carrot. In other words, it is the total input costs (including costs of labour), not the amount of labour per se, which create the difference in costs (and, therefore minimal equilibrium prices) of the goods. Marx however argues in the first chapters of Das Kapital that most of such costs (i.e. insofar as they refer to reproducible goods) are again reducible to direct and indirect costs in human labour time. When we see a car, we do not see the worldwide cooperation of labour-efforts that produced it at a certain cost, yet those labour efforts, weighed against other labour efforts, determine its value.

Austrian economics

Austrian economics explicitly rejects the objectivity of the values of goods as logically and conceptually unsound. On this view, we cannot validly say that products took a certain amount of labour, energy and materials to make, and compare them on that basis. It follows that the Austrian school thinks most contemporary economic theory is invalid, as it relies in one way or another on the aggregation and comparison of actual and ideal prices. This is forcefully argued by Friedrich von Hayek who therefore was skeptical about the objectivity of macroeconomic aggregations as such.[84] However, this raises the question of "what is the explanatory power of Austrian economics", if all we can say about a realized price is that it expresses a subjective preference, given that there are billions of subjective preferences which are all different.[85]

Ecologists

Ecologists and environmentalists have criticized Marx on the ground that natural resources have (or should have) a value which has nothing to do with production costs in labour time, because in fact they are entropic non-reproducible goods.[86] However, Marx himself never denied this; he was merely referring to the bourgeois valuation scheme, originating from commercial trade, double-entry bookkeeping and the theory of prices.[87]

Precisely because natural resources were for a long time either non-reproducible or freely available goods (i.e. not reproducible commodities) the whole tendency of the market economy was for those resources to be plundered for private gain, rather than economized appropriately.[88] Their "value" became apparent, only when they became scarce, and had somehow to be maintained, restored, recycled or reproduced. Moreover, the only way a market economy has to "value" natural resources was to impute a notional money-price to them.

This resource price, however calculated, can only be based on one of three variables (or a combination of them): the cost-price of its appropriation, or the cost-price of substituting an alternative resource; the demand for it from buyers, and what they could pay for it; and the (potential) income that could be obtained from owning and selling it. These three variables therefore necessarily refer back to the existing cost- and price-structures, as well as the property rights within the market economy that already exist, and therefore, indirectly, the pricing does refer back to the results of the economizing of human labour-time which has already been achieved.

The only alternatives the bourgeois state has, are either to prohibit exploitation of the natural resource, to modify property rights (access) with respect to the resource, or to impose a tax levy of some type on their exploitation - with the aim of ensuring better stewardship of the natural resource. Such policies however are not formed independently of the existing economy; they have to respond to valuations which exist already. Generally speaking, rich people buy the nice places to be, while the poor live in what Mike Davis (scholar) calls the "planet of slums".[89]

Ecologists also note that Marxist theories of value caused large-scale environmental problems in the industrialization of the Soviet Union[90] China[91] and other countries ruled by communist parties; thus, whether or not an economy is a market economy or a state economy does not seem to make much difference, the problem is rather with the values of human cultures themselves or with industrialization processes as such. This more complex debate[92] cannot be dealt with in this article; it may be noted only that newly industrializing countries to a large extent imitated technical methods used in industrialized countries, and that Marx can hardly be held responsible for all the things done in his name - he had explicitly referred to problems of environmental despoilation quite a number of times, including in Das Kapital.[93] He never dealt systematically with socialist economics, amongst other things because he lacked an evidential basis for theorizing about that.[94]

Logical criticism

The logical criticism revolves around the idea that Marx is unable to reconcile the domain of value relations and the domain of price relations, showing exactly how value magnitudes correspond to price magnitudes.

Transformation problem

Various arguments are made to show that Marx's theory of value is logically incoherent. The most famous of these is the controversy about Marx's prices of production, sometimes called the transformation problem in which it is argued that total output value must equal total output prices, and total profits must equal total surplus value, so that the distributions of particular output values and output prices can then be inferred from each other, via mathematical functions and a tidy accounting sum, assuming the same rate of profit on capital invested by all sectors.[95] Since, however, this exercise gives rise either to logical problems which have never been satisfactorily resolved, or to an unmanageably large string of assumptions and variables, it is argued that Marx's theory should be abandoned.

Specifically, it cannot be proved, whether logically or empirically, that the total output value is equivalent to total output prices, and on that ground alone, many critics argue, there is already no proof that there is any necessary quantitative relationship between them (Marx simply assumes that relationship, but does not prove it). If that is so, then, the critics argue, there is no sense in which the Marxian product-values can explain market prices for products as the determinants of those prices. An additional problem discovered in mathematical modelling is that the assumption of the identity of total prices and total values (or the identity of total surplus value and total profits) cannot be maintained simultaneously with the assumption that the rate of profit on production capital is the same for all industries.[96] Marx is left saying "e pur si muove".

Uniform rate of profit?

But although this is often overlooked by economists[97] Marx himself used a uniform rate of profit for all industries in Capital Vol. 3 only for modelling purposes, to show in a simple way how the ruling profit rates on capital impacted on the development of production system, and he explicitly denied that a uniform rate of profit obtained in reality; he only argued that at any time there would exist an average "minimum acceptable" profit rate on capital invested in industries, and if there was no realistic possibility at all of reaching at least that profit rate sometime in the future, capital would very likely be disinvested after a while, since the relevant business would then simply lack commercial viability; alternatively, the business would be taken over, and restructured to restore an acceptable profit rate. This minimum profit rate applying to new investments is closely linked to the ruling interest rates applicable to producing enterprises;[98] if the interest rate is e.g. 5%, then the industrial profit rate on production capital must net at least 10% (or more), otherwise investors are likely to keep their money in the bank, or buy other assets.[99] Thus Marx writes:

"The general rate of profit, however, appears only as the lowest limit of profit, not as an empirical, directly visible form of the actual rate of profit."[100]

Aggregate identities

Marx and Engels also explicitly denied that in reality total product-value would be equal to the total of product-prices (see prices of production). Such an "accounting identity" was ruled out in the real world by continual variations in labour productivity and because, at any time, no competitive force existed that could exactly cancel out the difference between goods sold above value and goods sold below value.[101] It was also ruled out by the imperfections of the price-form itself, which, the fetishization of price statistics notwithstanding, permitted the expression of product-values only in an approximate way (see real prices and ideal prices). At best - Marx assumed - there was a reasonably close correspondence between total product-value and total product-prices. He believed economic fluctuations implied that if some products were sold under their value, this necessarily meant that other products were sold above their value.[102]

The divergence between total product-values and total product-prices on the whole was, Marx believed, probably not so very large, in an open, competitive market, where enormous price-value discrepancies were ordinarily impossible to maintain commercially for any length of time (among other things because in that case people would exchange very large amounts of work for very small amounts of work; they might be prepared to do that for some products, but not for most of them, because they simply could not afford to do so). But that is something which is very difficult - if not impossible - to prove. At best one could estimate the relationship between average product prices and the average cost in labour time which it currently takes to make them, for a large range of products, and then analyze the statistical correlations between unit prices and average costs in labour time; if no positive correlation exists, the theory is false.

In the real world, ultimately nothing stays constant except the progress of time, which we can measure with clocks;[104] all the economic variables are constantly moving and fluctuating. To prove an identity of total output values and total output production prices, we would require a counting unit of value which can be specified independently from money-prices, but we cannot specify that unit in that way. That unit can exist only as a theoretical entity (or as an ideal price comparable to an empirical price) which is also exactly how Marx used it in his simplified illustrations of value relationships. He simply uses a number for the value-quantity and another number for the price-quantity, to indicate a proportion. Empirically, one can only get as far as establishing a "grand average" for the price of an hour of work (this is often referred to as the "monetary equivalent of labour time", or MELT) and one can discuss the extent to which labour is undervalued or overvalued in a relative (comparative) sense.[105]

Stochastic analysis

Product-values in Marx's sense quite simply cannot be directly observed, only inferred from the actual behaviour of trading relations.[106] Product-values manifest themselves and can only be expressed as trading ratios, (ideal) prices, or quantities of labour-time, and therefore the academic "transformation controversy" is according to many modern Marxist theorists misguided; it rests simply on a false interpretation of the relationship between the value-form of commodities and the price-form.[107] As soon as we admit that product-prices may fluctuate above or below product-values for all kinds of reasons - a central determinant of market dynamics - the quantitative relationship between values and prices is at best probabilistic, not a fixed function of some type. Marx himself actually made this perfectly explicit already in 1844, long before he began work on Das Kapital:

"...James Mill commits the mistake - like the school of Ricardo in general - of stating the abstract law without the change or continual supersession of this law through which alone it comes into being. If it is a constant law that, for example, the cost of production in the last instance - or rather when demand and supply are in equilibrium which occurs sporadically, fortuitously - determines the price (value), it is just as much a constant law that they are not in equilibrium, and that therefore [new] value and cost of production stand in no necessary relationship. Indeed, there is always only a momentary equilibrium of demand and supply owing to the previous fluctuation of demand and supply, [and] owing to the disproportion between cost of production and [the] exchange-value [of new products], just as this fluctuation and this disproportion likewise again follow the momentary state of equilibrium. This real movement, of which that law is only an abstract, fortuitous and one-sided factor, is made by recent political economy into something accidental and inessential. Why? Because in the acute and precise formulas to which they reduce political economy, the basic formula, if they wished to express that movement abstractly, would have to be: in political economy, law is determined by its opposite, absence of law. The true law of political economy is chance, from whose movement we, the scientific men, isolate certain factors arbitrarily in the form of laws." - Karl Marx, Comments on JamesMill, Éléments D'économie Politique (1844) [57] (note: this official English translation is not quite accurate).[108]

The structure of Marx's argument in Capital Vol. 3 is that there is a constant contradiction in capitalism between the inescapable labour-costs incurred to produce products, and the laws of price competition which create pressure to maximize the return on capital invested - a contradiction which must constantly be mediated in practice, bringing about the "real movement" of the production system (ideally, capitalists would prefer just to trade assets without the nuisance and trouble of hiring labor, but the assets have to be produced, that production requires labor, and therefore that labor has to be organized in a commercially effective way).[109]

Limitations of proofs

The only way to transcend the scientific "arbitrariness" to which the young Marx already referred, was by understanding and theorizing the dynamics of the capitalist system as a whole, integrating all the different economic forces at work into a unified, coherent theory that could withstand the test of scientific criticism.[110] Thus, Marx's value theory offers an interpretation, generalisation or explanation concerning the "grand averages" of the relative price movements of products, and of economic behaviour in capitalist production as a social system, but it is not possible to deduce specific real product-prices from product-values according to some mathematical function, among other things because, to find labour-values, a relationship between product-prices and labour hours worked must already be assumed. What we can verify is:

No logical proof of a concept of economic value has ever been possible; the concept proved its utility only by coherently explaining the phenomena of value, and by its ability to predict how economic behaviour would empirically evolve. It is of course also possible that Marx's bold attempt at a unified grand theory - a Popperian "bold hypothesis" which he did not actually finish for publication himself - is partly correct and partly incorrect. The idealisations of the simpified "pure" model, which aim to identify the interaction of the main operative forces, may not adequately capture how things work out in empirical reality - it may tell us only "where to look" for an explanation. In this sense, Andrew Glyn commented:

"The world economy is too complicated and there are too many different causal factors. I don't believe, as I used to, that Marx's concepts should be applied too literally to economic data. I prefer the view of the Japanese Uno school that Marx's analysis should rather inform one's way of looking at the world and the questions one asks. The first volume of Capital, for example, provides a brilliant framework for understanding what is happening in China today."[112]

Empirical criticism

The empirical criticism is simply that there is no observable quantitative correspondence at all between changes in relative expenditures of labour-time, and changes in relative market prices of products, however measured (the measures are also contested, for example on the ground that qualitatively different kinds of labour cannot be compared and equated). This is undoubtedly the strongest criticism, but there exists as yet very little research to back it up.[113] Most critics have tried to refute Marx's theory with an elegant mathematical model, rather than actually looking at real data to see if the capitalist economy really behaves in the way Marx claims it does.[114]

Of course, Marx is not talking about all prices,[115] only about a theory of the formation of production prices of new output (which may deviate themselves from actual market prices, and may be observable only by comparing price aggregates during an interval of time). It is essentially an argument about the "deep structure" of product markets. One scientific difficulty in empirical research is that in order to compute an empirical proxy variable for the "labour-value" magnitude, a relationship between input/output price data and data on labour hours worked has to be inferred, from official statistics which themselves are calculated using many valuation and estimation assumptions, without it being very clear what the margin of error is likely to be.

Responses to criticism

These three lines of criticism lead the critics to the conclusion that Marx's law of value is metaphysical and theoretically useless. Everything he says can be restated in terms of prices, real or ideal, so what is the point then of any theory of "value"?

Austrian economics

Austrian economics goes a step further by attributing no special objective meaning to price levels at all, which it considers a mere "statistical outcome" of comparisons between each party's ratios between the value of money (taken to be just another kind of a good) to values of goods being sold or purchased. The prices, therefore, are knowledge, which may (or may not) influence behaviour of economic agents differently in each particular case. However, this approach is inconsistent, insofar as nothing in their theory entitles the Austrians to aggregate prices at all; because each price expresses a unique subjective preference, adding up prices is like adding up apples and pears.

Why is a value theory needed?

Marx himself thought that the concept of value was necessary to explain the historical origins, the development and mode of functioning of capitalism as a social system, under conditions where traded, priced assets were only a subset of total assets possessing a potential exchange-value.

What is the economy?

If the economy just consisted of prices, Marx's theory would be unnecessary, but it doesn't just consist of prices. It consists also of socially related working people creating and distributing wealth among each other, property rights enforced by the state, and a large stock of untraded assets in use or stored.

Accounting assumptions

Any price-accounting, calculation and aggregation could not even occur without the 7 concepts of value equivalence, value comparability, value transferred, conserved value, value used up, depreciated or destroyed (in general, reduction of value), value increase and newly created value. Any economist has to assume such basic categorical distinctions in some or other form, even if they are not made explicit in arguments about prices, or revealed by the price-form itself. By analogy, in mathematics, the validity of an equation assumes that the numbers used in it are part of a number set defined in the last instance by the categorical distinctions of number theory which imply operational rules for the use of numbers.

More simply, one can say that if a price expresses a valuation we cannot do without a concept of value. At most we can say that the price is the valuation, which is what economists typically do. But this leads to logical and explanatory problems, insofar as prices can then be explained only in terms of prices. As soon as prices cannot be explained anymore in terms of other prices, the economist is forced to resort to "extra-economic" factors outside his own science. Marx did not have that problem, because his theory is based on the social relationships between people, and the social-institutional framework within which they operate.

The price form

According to primitive economics, all prices are of the same kind and differ only quantitatively; they only express more or less money, and can only go up or down.[116] For Marx, this idea was not only false, but totally absurd, since different kinds of prices can assume different valuation principles, contractual obligations, conditionalities, inclusions/exclusions as well as relationships between economic actors. We can compute dozens of different prices for the same good, depending on what valuations assumptions we make; these prices refer to qualitatively different conditions. Marx noted that the forms prices take are highly variegated, and he drew a sharp distinction between real prices and ideal prices. Marx stated explicitly that price relationships can be such, that they do not reflect the true value relationship at all.[117] That is why businessmen assumed a theory of value, even if they were not aware that they were doing it. The scientific theory merely made explicit what they were implicitly assuming for the purpose of doing business.

Infinite regress

Marx asked questions like: if supply and demand are equal, what then explains the price-level? If goods trade at their real value, what explains the increase of value occurring in production? If competition settled a particular average profit rate, why that average level, and not any other? Price theory ended up in an infinite regress here, of explaining prices by other prices by other prices, and so on. But as soon as it was admitted that prices were the monetary expression of exchange-value in the trading process, one had to explain where that exchange-value came from, and how it was established. And that required a theory of economic value and trade.

Theoretical assumptions

The economists assumed all sorts of things about an economy and economic actors, in order to build models of price behaviour; Marx thought those assumptions themselves needed to be looked at and theorised consistently. However, his critics claim that his own approach has hidden assumptions as well, and that these assumptions contradict the empirically observable reality of human action. In the letter by Marx cited above, Marx anticipated this criticism, which he regarded as very shallow.[118]

The sun and the earth

For thousands of years, people believed that the sun revolved around the earth (after all, we can observe how the sun rises in the East and sets in the West) until science revealed that just the opposite was the case. It is perfectly possible not only to participate in market trade without much knowledge of markets and their overall effects, but also to participate in markets with a false or one-sided interpretation of what is really going on in the exchanges. In this sense, Marx warns that market trade can stimulate all sorts of delusions about what relationships are really involved.

Pure cases & ceteris paribus clauses

It is true that Marx often examined economic relationships abstractly, in the "purest" or "simplest" cases, "other things being equal", knowing very well that in empirical reality those relationships were modified by all sorts of influences. But this is a perfectly legitimate scientific procedure in theorizing, and typically he argued that, if one couldn't explain the simplest cases of an economic phenomenon, one couldn't explain all its variations either; in fact one couldn't explain anything at all. One can show, step by step, how the purest expression of a scientific law is modified by various circumstances, to the point where the intrinsic necessity of events is understood. That is indeed what Marx tried to do, although he never completed what he intended (ill health, overwork, exhaustion and poverty got in the way).[119]

Steve Keen and the machine

In his book Debunking Economics: The naked Emperor of the Social Sciences,[120] the Australian economist Steve Keen has attempted to counter Marx's theory (in his view Marx's pre-1857 view, specifically) from a post-Keynesian perspective, by arguing that machines can add more product-value over their operational lifetime than the total value of depreciation charged during those asset lives. For example, the total value of sausages produced by a sausage machine over its useful life might be greater than the value of the machine. Depreciation, he implies, was the weak point in Marx's social accounting system all along. Keen argues that all factors of production can add new value to outputs.

This raises the question of how we know which part of the new value is due directly to the worker, which part is due to the pork, and which part is due directly to the machine (or indirectly to any worker involved in the production of that machine) - none of which of course can produce products without the others, unless we suppose full automation.

Marx remained insistent that only human labour could create net new value, and that machines did not create any new value by themselves; instead human beings conserved the value of machines, and transferred their value to the new products. Therefore, logically, machines could contribute no more value than was implied by the labour it took to make them, or perhaps more precisely, by their current value in society. This value should of course be distinguished from that part of the output price charged as depreciation costs, i.e. a distinction should be drawn between depreciation in value terms and depreciation in price terms. The replacement costs of fixed equipment are influenced by developments in productivity within industries producing the equipment, developments which may be reflected in price-levels only with a certain time-lag.

That aside, Marxist economists such as Ernest Mandel have argued that owners of new, more productive fixed equipment (which the owners may monopolize with the aid of patents) can obtain extra income from its use, representing effectively an economic rent (so-called "technological rents").[121] Whatever view one takes, it is clear depreciation raises complex issues, because depreciation write-offs often do not reflect the "real" loss of value of a fixed asset, but rather the maximum value permitted by governments and auditors to be written off for tax purposes (for more discussion, see the OPE-L ("Outline of Political Economy") list [58] and Marx and Surplus Value ([59]).

See also

Sociology portal
Business and economics portal

References

  1. ^ See Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy, chapter 1 part 2 [1] where Marx refers to Proud hon's own "law of value" and chapter 3, titled “Application of the Law of the Proportionality of Value”.[2] For a commentary, see: Takahisi Oishi, The unknown Marx: reconstructing a unified perspective. Foreword by Terrell Carver. London: Pluto Press, 2001
  2. ^ "Marx formulates the law of value as follows: 'The magnitude of the value of any article is the amount of labor socially necessary, or the labor-time socially necessary, for its production.'" John Eaton, Political Economy: A Marxist Textbook. Rev ed. 1963 reprinted 1970. p. 29. "...the value of commodities is determined not by the labour-time originally taken by their production, but rather by the labour-time that their reproduction takes, and this steadily decreases as the social productivity of labour develops." - Marx, Capital, Volume III, Penguin ed., p. 522.
  3. ^ Isaak Illich Rubin, A History of Economic Thought. London: Ink Links, 1979.
  4. ^ ”Throughout this work I assume that gold is the money commodity, for the sake of simplicity.” – Karl Marx, Capital, Volume I, Penguin edition, chapter 3, p. 188. For a commentary, see: Ian Steedman, “Marx and Ricardo”, in: Ian Bradley and Michael Howard, Classical and Marxian Political Economy: Essays in honour of Ronald L. Meek. London: Macmillan, 1982, p. 120. Already in 1844, long before he wrote Das Kapital, Marx was very aware of credit money, noting that "The nations which are still dazzled by the sensuous glitter of precious metals, and are therefore still fetish-worshippers of metal money, are not yet fully developed money-nations. Contrast of France and England." Karl Marx, Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844, in Marx-Engels Collected Works, Vol. 3. Moscow: Progress, 1975, p. 312. In Capital, Volume II he comments that "In developed capitalist production, the money-economy appears only as the basis of the credit-economy. The money-economy and credit-economy thus correspond only to different stages in the development of capitalist production..." Capital Vol. 2, chapter 4. [3]. Thus, whereas "commodity money" (coinage or bullion) played an important role in the earlier stages of capitalist development, the growth of integrated capital markets meant increased use of credit money. Marx apparently felt that the assumption of gold-money was justified in analysing the capitalist relations of production and distribution, because whatever type of money was used, this did not alter the basic character of those relations.
  5. ^ When Ernest Mandel writes "For Marx, labour is value" (Karl Marx, Part 4[4] this is, strictly speaking, a mistake. For Marx, as Marx himself says explicitly, labour itself has no "value" in bourgeois society, only a price. Only the results of human work have value, that is to say, the labour has to materialize itself in some kind of object which has value, and can be owned for a price or a fee. The importance of labour is its ability to preserve capital value, increase already existing value, and create wholly new value.
  6. ^ See e.g. Ian Steedman et al., The Value Controversy. London: Verso, 1981; John Weeks, Capital and exploitation. Edward Arnold, 1981; Ernest Mandel, and Alan Freeman (eds.), Ricardo, Marx, Sraffa, The Langston Memorial Volume, London: Verso, 1984[5]; Makoto Itoh, The Basic Theory of Capitalism; Ulrich Krause, Money and Abstract Labour: On the Analytical Foundations of Political Economy. Translated by Peter Burgess. Edited by Jon Rothschild. London: Verso 1982; Alan Freeman, Andrew Kliman, Julian Wells (eds.), The new value controversy and the foundations of economics. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 2004; Simon Mohun (ed.), Debates in Value Theory. Macmillan: London, 1994; Richard Westra & Alan Zuege (eds.), Value and the world economy today - Production, Finance and Globalization. Houndmills: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003. Alfredo Saad-Filho, The value of Marx: political economy for contemporary capitalism. London: Routledge, 2002; Ajit Sinha, Theories of Value from Adam Smith to Piero Sraffa. London: Routledge, 2010.
  7. ^ See e.g. Alan Freeman & Guglielmo Carchedi, Marx and non-equilibrium economics. Cheltenham: Edward Elgar, 1996; Andrew Kliman, Reclaiming Marx's 'Capital': a refutation of the myth of inconsistency. Lanham: Lexington Books, 2007; Anwar Shaikh papers [6]; Gerard Duménil & Dominique Lévy papers [7]; Paul Cockshott, Ian Wright et al. Information, Money and Value [8]; Samir Amin, The Law of Value and Historical Materialism. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1978; Ian Wright, "The Emergence of the law of value in a dynamic simple commodity economy". Review of Political Economy, Vol. 20, No. 3, pages 367—391. [9]; Patrick Julian Wells, The rate of profit as a random variable. Phd dissertation, School of management, Open University, London 2007; Alfredo Saad Filho interview on value theory, Marx's idea of value. [10]; Andrew J. Kliman, "The law of value and laws of statistics: sectoral values and prices in the US economy, 1977--97". Cambridge Journal of Economics, 2002, vol. 26, issue 3, pages 299-311; Thomas T. Sekine, The Necessity of the Law of Value, its Demonstration and Significance[11]; Enrique Dussel, Towards an unknown Marx: a commentary on the manuscripts of 1861-63. London: Routledge, 2001. In recent years, the Italian Marxist scholar Riccardo Bellofiore and other members of the International Symposium on Marxian Theory (ISMT)[12] [13] have edited a number of volumes of scholarly commentaries on Marx's Capital, which benefit from the definitive MEGA II edition of Marx's works. However these books are extremely expensive, and only accessible to rich people since most libraries do not have copies. Alan Freeman has provided IWGVT papers online.[14]
  8. ^ Luigi Pasinetti, "The notion of vertical integration in economic analysis", in L. L. Pasinetti (ed.), Essays on the theory of joint production. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1980.
  9. ^ ”Or are we to believe that peasant and village artisans were so stupid that one of them would part with the product of ten hours labour for that of a single hour?” – Friedrich Engels, Supplement to Volume 3 of Capital, in Marx, Capital, Volume III, Penguin, p. 1035.
  10. ^ I.I. Rubin, Essays on Marx's theory of value (Montreal: Black Rose Books, 1990), chapter 15, note 15, p. 166: "Marx's goal was not to subsume the price of unreproducible objects under the law of value. He did not do this because of the simple reason that the law of value has to explain precisely the laws of human productive activities. In his theory of value, Marx does not treat the value of products which 'cannot be reproduced by labor, such as antiques and works of art by certain masters, etc.'"
  11. ^ The Marxist doctrine about the "domination of the law of value" originated with Yevgeni Preobrazhensky's book The new economics (1926). Clarendon Press, 1965. Marx himself never said that people were "dominated by the law of value", but rather that they were dominated by the movements of Capital. In modern Marxism, the law of value is often equated with "market economy", but that was not Marx's own idea.
  12. ^ Karl Marx, Capital, Volume III, Penguin, Part 6, pp. 751-1026.
  13. ^ See: Ernest Mandel, The second slump: a Marxist analysis of recession in the seventies. London: Verso, 1978.
  14. ^ "When you are poor, you are willing to trade your time to earn money. When you are rich, you trade your money to get more time." Scott Adams, "How to tax the rich", Wall Street Journal, 29 January 2011.
  15. ^ In Capital, Volume I, Marx argues that Aristotle was unable to reach an understanding of abstract labour because of the inequalities between slave labour and free labour in ancient Greek society (Penguin e.d, p. 151-152). In the Grundrisse Marx opines that ”As a rule, the most general abstractions arise only in the midst of the richest possible concrete development, where one thing appears as common to many, to all. Then it ceases to be thinkable in a particular form alone. (…) Bourgeois society is the most developed and most complex historic organization of production. The categories which express its relations, the comprehension of its structure, thereby also allow insights into the structure and the relations of production of all the vanished social formations out of whose ruins and elements it built itself up, whose partly still unconquered remnants are carried along within it, whose mere nuances have developed explicit significance within it, etc.” – Marx, Grundrisse, Penguin ed., p. 105.
  16. ^ Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations, Book I, chapter 6.
  17. ^ Utz-Peter Reich, National Accounts and Economic Value: A Study in Concepts. London: Palgrave/Macmillan, 2001, p. 1.
  18. ^ Paul A. Samuelson, 'Understanding the Marxian notion of exploitation: a summary of the so-called transformation problem between Marxian values and competitive prices', Journal of Economic Literature, 9, 1971: 399-431.
  19. ^ Ronald L. Meek, Studies in the Labour Theory of Value. Monthly Review Press, 2nd ed., 1976, p. 70.
  20. ^ Karl Marx, Value, Price and Profit More or less the same point is made by Marx again in Capital, Volume III, chapter 10 Penguin edition, p. 291: "If two forces act in opposing directions and cancel one another out, they have no external impact whatsoever, and phenomena that appear under these conditions must be explained otherwise than by the operation of these two forces. If demand and supply cancel one another out, they cease to explain anything, have no effect on market value and leave us completely in the dark as to why this market value is expressed in precisely such a sum of money and no other. The real inner laws of capitalist production clearly cannot be explained in terms of the interaction of demand and supply (not to mention the deeper analysis of these two social driving forces which we do not intend to give here), since these laws are realized in their pure form only when demand and supply cease to operate, i.e. when they coincide. In actual fact, demand and supply never coincide... political economy assume[s] that they do coincide... [i]n order to treat the phenomena it deals with in their law-like form..." etc.
  21. ^ David Ricardo, Principles of Political Economy and Taxation, chapter 1.[15]
  22. ^ See further Geoffrey Pilling, "The law of value in Ricardo and Marx", Economy & Society, Vol 1, issue 3, 1972, pp. 281-307. Marx never argued that the law of value balances out the trading process, but rather that it regulates the trading process. “The production of commodities must be fully developed before the scientific conviction emerges, from experience itself, that all the different kinds of private labour (which are carried on independently of each other, and yet, as spontaneously developed branches of the social division of labour, are in a situation of all-round dependence on each other) are continually being reduced to the quantitative proportions in which society requires them.The reason for this reduction is that in the midst of the accidental and ever-fluctuating exchange relations between the products, the labour-time socially necessary to produce them asserts itself as a regulative law of nature. In the same way, the law of gravity asserts itself when a person's house collapses on top of him. The determination of the magnitude of value by labour-time is therefore a secret hidden under the apparent movements in the relative values of commodities. Its discovery destroys the semblance of the merely accidental determination of the magnitude of the value of the products of labour, but by no means abolishes that determination's material form.” – Marx, Capital, Volume I, Penguin, p. 168.
  23. ^ See the quotation by Marx provided in the text below.
  24. ^ Karl Marx, Theories of surplus-value, chapter 3, section 4.[16] By "the law of value changing into its opposite", Marx meant that while in simple commodity production the producer offers his product for sale at a price reflecting his own labour and materials costs, in capitalist production the social valuation of the product confronts the producer as an objective market law. In addition, capitalist exchange is not an exchange of labour-equivalents; rather, capitalists try to sell products at competitive prices below their value, while making a good profit, the long-term result of which is that all commodities decline in value. In simple commodity production and exchange, the producer is rewarded according to the amount of hours he puts in himself. But in capitalist production, capitalists are rewarded according to the amount of capital they own and use, and according to how productive the employed labour is. The more capitalists produce with less labour, the more income capitalists get.
  25. ^ Karl Marx, Capital, Volume I, Penguin edition, p. 421. Marx goes into more detail about this issue in Theories of Surplus Value.
  26. ^ Friedrich Engels, Preface to Capital, Volume II, Penguin edition, p. 101.
  27. ^ The underlying idea was, that it is in the nature of markets themselves to establish the true expression of the value or cost of products, simply through successive adjustments of demand and supply towards a naturally balanced state. Even if, due to all kinds of factors, balance was never achieved exactly, Smith and Ricardo believed that a "natural price level" could nevertheless be assumed for each kind of product. Marx considered this essentially a metaphysical (untestable) solution, but it did not especially surprise him - for if the political economists had followed their own law of value idea to its final scientific conclusion, then - Marx suggests - they would have had to change their whole understanding of capitalism radically. This they were not prepared to do.
  28. ^ For example, when Marx analyzes wages conceptually as an economic form (as a social institution) in Capital, Volume I, he emphasizes very explicitly that "All the notions of justice held by both the worker and the capitalist, all the mystifications of the capitalist mode of production, all capitalism's illusions of freedom, all the apologetic tricks of vulgar economics, have as their basis the form of appearance discussed above, which makes the actual relation invisible, and indeed presents to the eye the precise opposite of that relation" (Penguin ed., p. 680). He explains how the market relationship by its very nature inverts the real social relationship involved, so that it appears as its very opposite. He applies the same kind of argument in Capital to many different economic "forms", in order to demonstrate how the very nature of an institutionalized practice itself causes a misapprehension of its true significance, so that things appear other than they are. The real significance becomes apparent only when, through an historical study of the origin of the "form", one becomes clearly aware of what is actually involved in the emergence of the form, i.e. the conditions necessary for its existence and perpetuation. Marx presents this argument not as a metaphysical "philosophy of essentialism", but as a scientifically testable argument with explanatory and predictive power. The Marxist doctrine of Marx's theory as a "theory of objective value" originated with the non-Marxist Werner Sombart, who reviewed Capital Vol. 3, as Nikolai Bukharin acknowledged in his Economic theory of the leisure class (1927), chapter 1.[17]
  29. ^ Marc Linder, Reification and the consciousness of the critics of political economy. Copenhagen: Rhodos, 1975.
  30. ^ ”The value-form, whose fully developed shape is the money-form, is very simple and slight in content. Nevertheless, the human mind has sought in vain for more than 2,000 years to get to the bottom of it, while on the other hand there has been at least an approximation to a successful analysis of forms which are much richer in content and more complex.” –Marx, Capital, Volume I, Penguin, p. 90.
  31. ^ Ian Steedman thus argued value theory was unnecessary, since everything can be stated in terms of prices. See: Ian Steedman, Marx after Sraffa. London: NLB, 1977.
  32. ^ See Karl Marx, Theories of Surplus Value (3 Vols.) and the Grundrisse manuscript.
  33. ^ See Thomas T. Sekine, “Marxian theory of value, what we might learn from it”, in: Korean Journal of Political Economy, Volume 2, 2004, pp. 1-35.
  34. ^ a b Paul Mattick, Marx and Keynes, chapter 5
  35. ^ ”It is true that the different spheres of production constantly tend towards equilibrium, for the following reason. On the one hand, every producer of a commodity is obliged to produce a use-value, i.e. he must satisfy a particular social need (though the extent of these needs differs quantitatively, and there exists an inner bond which attaches the different levels of need to a system which has grown up spontaneously); on the other hand, the law of the value of commodities ultimately determines how much of its disposable labour-time society can expend on each kind of commodity. But this constant tendency on the part of the various spheres of production towards equilibrium comes into play only as a reaction against the constant upsetting of this equilibrium. The planned and regulated a priori system on which the division of labour is implemented within the workshop becomes, in the division of labour within society, an a posteriori necessity imposed by nature, controlling the unregulated caprice of the producers, and perceptible in the fluctuations of the barometer of market prices.” – Marx, Capital, Volume I, Penguin, p. 476.
  36. ^ See Marx, Capital, Volume II. Penguin, 1978.
  37. ^ See: Geoff Kay and James Mott, Public Order and the Law of Labour;. London: Macmillan, 1982.
  38. ^ "The maintenance and reproduction of the working-class is, and must ever be, a necessary condition to the reproduction of capital. But the capitalist may safely leave its fulfilment to the labourer's instincts of self-preservation and of propagation. All the capitalist cares for, is to reduce the labourer's individual consumption as far as possible to what is strictly necessary, and he is far away from imitating those brutal South Americans, who force their labourers to take the more substantial, rather than the less substantial, kind of food." - Marx, Capital, Volume I, chapter 23.
  39. ^ "Coining, like the establishment of a standard of prices, is the business of the State. (...) Being a transient and objective reflex of the prices of commodities, [money] serves only as a symbol of itself, and is therefore capable of being replaced by a token. One thing is, however, requisite; this token must have an objective social validity of its own, and this the paper symbol acquires by its forced currency. This compulsory action of the State can take effect only within that inner sphere of circulation which is coterminous with the territories of the community, but it is also only within that sphere that money completely responds to its function of being the circulating medium, or becomes coin." Capital, Volume I, chapter 3, section C [18].
  40. ^ ”If… the German reader pharisaically shrugs his shoulders at the condition of the English industrial and agricultural workers, or optimistically comforts himself with the thought that in Germany things are not nearly so bad, I must plainly tell him: De te fabula narratur![The tale is told of you] Intrinsically, it is not a question of the higher or lower degree of development of the social antagonisms that spring from the natural laws of capitalist production. It is a question of these laws themselves, of these tendencies winning their way through and working themselves out with iron necessity. The country that is more developed industrially only shows, to the less developed, the image of its own future.” – Marx, Capital, Volume I, Penguin, p. 91.
  41. ^ This formulation was used by Paul Mattick.
  42. ^ Christian Girschner, Politische Ökonomie und Weltmarkt; Allgemeine Weltmarktdynamik in der Marxschen Kritik der politischen Ökonomie. Cologne: Papyrossa, 1999.
  43. ^ Paul Bairoch, Victoires et deboires, Vol. 3, Gallimard 1997, p. 699). Gross profit in Marx's sense has three main components: the fees of corporate officers; undistributed profit used to finance investment; and profit distributed as dividends to shareholders or owners. A fraction of income from depreciation write-offs (where government incentive schemes are applicable) and net increases in the value of inventories may also be counted as part of gross profit.
  44. ^ Marx, Capital, Volume I, Penguin, chapter 7.
  45. ^ Marx, Capital, Volume III. Penguin, 1981, Part 2, pp. 241-375.
  46. ^ Capital, Volume III, chapter 1, emphasis added
  47. ^ Marx, Capital, Volume III, Penguin ed. 1981, Part 3.
  48. ^ In the Communist Manifesto, Marx and Engels state somewhat rhetorically: “The bourgeoisie, during its rule of scarce one hundred years, has created more massive and more colossal productive forces than have all preceding generations together. Subjection of Nature's forces to man, machinery, application of chemistry to industry and agriculture, steam-navigation, railways, electric telegraphs, clearing of whole continents for cultivation, canalisation of rivers, whole populations conjured out of the ground -- what earlier century had even a presentiment that such productive forces slumbered in the lap of social labor?”
  49. ^ Josef Steindl, Maturity and Stagnation in American Capitalism. New York: Monthly Review Press, 1952.
  50. ^ karl Marx, Capital, Volume III, Penguin edition, p. 280.
  51. ^ |"We have seen that the price of production of a commodity is not at all identical with its value, although the prices of production of commodities, considered in their totality, are regulated only by their total value, and although the movement of production prices of various kinds of commodities, all other circumstances being equal, is determined exclusively by the movement of their values.” – Marx, Capital, Volume III, chapter 45 [19].
  52. ^ Remarks by Federal Reserve Board Chairman Alan Greenspan before the Bundesbank, lecture 2004, Berlin, Germany, January 13, 2004 [20]
  53. ^ Adam Smith, The Wealth of Nations, p. ?
  54. ^ "Onnce we understand that the famous 'invisible hand' which is supposed to regulate supply and demand on the market is nothing but the operation of that same law of value, we can tie together a whole series of economic processes which otherwise remain disconected pieces of analysis." - Ernest Mandel, "Introduction" to Capital, Volume I, Penguin edition 1976, p. 41.
  55. ^ See Karl Marx, Theories of Surplus Value, chapter 3.[21]
  56. ^ W. Paul Cockshott and Allin F. Cottrell, "Value's Law, Value's Metric", September, 1994. [22]
  57. ^ Five years after this part on Soros was introduced into this wikipedia article, New School professor Anwar M. Shaikh published an excellent theoretical and econometric discussion of this topic, written especially for economists. See: Anwar Shaikh, "Reflexivity, Path-Dependence and Disequilibrium Dynamics." in: Journal of Post Keynesian Economics, Vol. 33, No. 1, 2010. [23]
  58. ^ George Soros,The Crisis of Global Capitalism (1998), Chapter 3, Dutch edition, p. 83).
  59. ^ Karl Marx, Capital, Volume I, Penguin edition, p. 702.
  60. ^ The Marxist Ernest Mandel argued that even before differentials in productivity between nations became apparent through foreign trade, there already existed regional disparities within countries; these disparities tended to fade with more market integration. See: Ernest Mandel, Capitalism and Regional Disparities. Toronto: Hogtown Press pamphlet, 1971, reprinted under the same title in: Southwest Economy and Society, Vol. 1, 1976.
  61. ^ See Anwar Shaikh, “Values and Value transfers: A Comment on Itoh.”[24] and Enrique Dussel & Anibal Yanez, "Marx's economic manuscripts of 1861-63 and the 'concept' of dependency". Latin American Perspectives, Vol. 17 No. 2, Spring 1990, pp. 62-101, as well as the literature cited in the article on unequal exchange.
  62. ^ See *Oliver Nachtwey and Tobias ten Brink, "Lost in Transition: the German World-Market Debate in the 1970s". Historical Materialism, issue 16, 2008, pp. 37–70; Christel Neusüß, Imperialismus und Weltmarktbewegung des Kapitals. Erlangen: Politladen, 1972; Wolfgang Schoeller, Weltmarkt und Reproduktion des Kapitals. Frankfurt: EVA, 1976; Tilla Siegel, Kapitalismus als Weltsystem; Tilla Siegel, "Politics and Economics in the Capitalist World Market: Methodological Problems of Marxist Analysis", in: International Journal of Sociology, Vol. XIV, no. 1., Spring 1984; Klaus Busch, Die Multinationalen Konzerne. Zur Analyse der Weltmarktbewegung des Kapitals. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1974; Klaus Busch, Gunther Grunert, and Walter Tobergte, Strukturen der Kapitalistischen Weltoekonomie; Gunther Grunert, Technologische Innovationen und internationaler Handel; Henrike Hilwig, Wertgesetz und Wirtschaftssystem- Probleme der Preisbildung in warenproduzierenden Gesellschaften. Frankfurt: Campus, 1977. Fritz Helmedag, Warenproduktion mittels Arbeit - Zur Rehabilitation des Wertgesetzes. Marburg: Metropol Verlag, 1992; Wissenschaftlicher Streit um die modifiezierten durchsetzungsformen des Wertgesetzes auf dem Weltmarkt[25]
  63. ^ See Anwar Shaikh's work), (Samir Amin)'s work in France, and Makoto Itoh's Japanese work available in English.
  64. ^ Guglielmo Carchedi, For Another Europe: A Marxist Analysis of the EU. London: Verso, 2001; Branko Horvat, The theory of international trade; an alternative approach. Palgrave Macmillan, 1999; John Weeks, "International Exchange and the Causes of Backwardness", in Latin American Perspectives VI (Spring 1978)[26]
  65. ^ See Jayati Ghosh, “Why more Exports have not made Developing Countries Richer”[27]
  66. ^ "The test of whether a market has fully formed is whether all customers get the same items at the same price, allowing for transaction and transportation costs. (This condition, called the law of one price, was originally advanced by Adam Smith.) Such market conditions have long existed at a global level for natural commodities, such as crude oil, bauxite, and iron ore, as well as for manufactured commodities, such as petroleum, aluminum, and steel. The law of one price also exists for freely traded foreign exchange and most instruments traded in the capital market. It does not exist for labor, however—which is the fundamental structural issue the global economy faces. To understand labor’s role, of course, you need to understand arbitrage. Cross-border arbitrage in the financial economy focuses on tradable instruments denominated in various currencies. In the real economy, such arbitrage focuses on capturing differences in the cost of production across geographies. As markets have opened and transaction and transportation costs fallen over the past quarter century, arbitrage opportunities in global financial markets and commodities have been quickly exhausted, so they easily meet the global law-of-one-price test. Yet there are still enormous arbitrage opportunities available in labor rates: the cost of performing the same job in different nations can vary significantly. As a result, multinational corporations that are able to source their production in emerging markets can enjoy large labor cost savings." - Lowell Bryan, "Globalization’s critical imbalances". McKinsey Quarterly, June 2010.
  67. ^ See Anwar Shaikh, “Foreign trade and the law of value.”[28] [29] [30]
  68. ^ Letter of Karl Marx to Ludwig Kugelmann, London, 11 July 1868 (MECW, Volume 43, p. 67).[31]
  69. ^ Supplementary Afterword to Capital, Volume III
  70. ^ Joseph Stalin, Economic Problems of Socialism in the USSR.
  71. ^ Karl Marx, Capital, Volume III
  72. ^ Włodzimierz Brus, The market in a socialist economy. London: Routledge, 1972.
  73. ^ Andre Gunder Frank, "In Memoriam: Tribute To Ernest Mandel" [32]; John Lister, The Fallacies of State Capitalism: Ernest Mandel and Chris Harman Debate the USSR. Socialist Outlook, 1991.
  74. ^ Ernest Mandel, "The Laws of Motion of the Soviet Economy". In: Review of Radical Political Economics, Vol. 13, No. 1,Spring 1981, pages 35-39.[33]
  75. ^ Bertram Silverman, Man and Socialism in Cuba; The Great Debate. New York: Atheneum, 1971.
  76. ^ John Weeks, Capital and exploitation. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981.
  77. ^ Karl Marx, Capital, Volume I, Penguin edition, p. 1038.
  78. ^ Ernest Mandel, Marxist Economic Theory. Monthly Review Press, 1969; Kozo Uno, Principles of Political Economy. Harvester Press, 1980. Marx himself states: "Apart from the way in which the law of value governs prices and their movement, it is also quite apposite to view the values of commodities not only as theoretically prior to the prices of production, but also as historically prior to them. This applies to those conditions in which the means of production belong to the worker, and this condition is to be found, in both the ancient and the modern world., among peasant proprietors and handicraftsmen who work for themselves. This agrees, moreover, with the opinion which we have expressed previously, viz. that the development of products into commodities arises from the exchange between different communities, and not between the members of one and the same community." - Karl Marx, Capital, Volume III, Penguin ed., p. 277-278. In Theories of Surplus Value, chapter 3, section 4, Marx argues that Adam Smith failed to understand how the law of value applying to simple commodity exchange was "turned into its opposite" in capitalist exchange.[34]
  79. ^ See Marx, Grundrisse, chapter 2 [35]. In Capital, Volume I, Marx states: “I have elsewhere discussed exhaustively the shallow utopianism of the idea of 'labour-money' in a society founded on the production of commodities”. (Penguin ed., p. 188). see also: Alfredo Saad-Filho, "Labour, money and 'labour-money: a review of Marx's critique of John Gray's monetary analysis'", History of political economy, Vol. 25, issue 1, 1993, pp. 65-84.
  80. ^ See e.g. the works of János Kornai.
  81. ^ Simon Clarke, Marx, Marginalism and Modern Sociology: From Adam Smith to Max Weber. Palgrave Macmillan, 1991.
  82. ^ Eugen von Bohm-Bawerk, Karl Marx and the close of his system, followed by Bohm Bawerk's criticism of Marx, by Rudolf Hilferding. Porcupine Press, 1984.[36]
  83. ^ "Every trader knows, that he is far from having turned his goods into money, when he has expressed their value in a price or in imaginary money, and that it does not require the least bit of real gold, to estimate in that metal millions of pounds' worth of goods. When, therefore, money serves as a measure of value, it is employed only as imaginary or ideal money. This circumstance has given rise to the wildest theories." - Marx, Capital Vol. 1, ch 3, section 1. [37]
  84. ^ Friedrich von Hayek, Individualism and economic order. London: Routledge, 1948. "The Austrians define the cost of a commodity not in terms of inputs like labour time, which can in principle be measured objectively, but in terms of the alternative output which the same resources could be used to produce. Assessment of the value of this alternative output can only be made subjectively by each individual. It follows that the most important knowledge driving the economic system is individual, subjective, decentralized, and therefore inaccessible to any central authority" - Andrew Gamble, Hayek: the iron cage of liberty. Westview Press, 1996, p. 67-68.
  85. ^ See further e.g. Bruce Caldwell, Hayek's Challenge: an intellectual biography of F.A. Hayek. University of Chicago Press, 2004, part 3.
  86. ^ See e.g. Harry Rothman, Murderous providence; a study of pollution in industrial societies. London: R. Hart-Davis, 1972; Elmar Altvater, Gesellschaftliche Produktion und ökonomische Rationalität - Externe Effekte und zentrale Planung im Wirtschaftssystem des Sozialismus. Frankfurt: EVA, 1969; Barry Commoner, The closing circle : confronting the environmental crisis. London: Cape, 1972; Andre Gorz, Ecology as Politics. South End Press, 1979.
  87. ^ Ernest Mandel, "La dialectique de la croissance: à propos du rapport Mansholt". In: Mai (Bruxelles), 1972 (Nov./Dec.): pp. 7–14. Translated as "Marxismus und Ekologie" in: Ernest Mandel, Karl Marx: die Aktualität seines Werkes, ed. Willy Boepple. Cologne: ISP verlag, 1984.
  88. ^ John Bellamy Foster, Marx's Ecology: Materialism and Nature. Monthly Review Press, 2000.
  89. ^ Mike Davis, "Planet of slums; urban involution and the informal proletariat". New Left Review, #26, March-April 2004, pp. 5-34.[38]
  90. ^ Boris Komarov, The Destruction of Nature in the Soviet Union. Pluto Press, 1980
  91. ^ Vaclav Smil, China's Environmental Crisis: An Inquiry into the Limits of National Development. M.E. Sharpe, 1982; Judith Shapiro, Mao's War against Nature: Politics and the Environment in Revolutionary China. Cambridge University Press, 2001.
  92. ^ For some thoughtful insights into the current controversies, see: Daniel Ben-Ami, Ferraris for all: in defence of progress. Polity Press, 2010 [39]; George Monbiot, Heat: How to Stop the Planet Burning. Allen Lane, 2006. [40]
  93. ^ "Capitalist production, therefore, develops technology, and the combining together of various processes into a social whole, only by sapping the original sources of all wealth — the soil and the labourer." - Karl Marx, Capital, Volume I, chapter 15 section 10.[41] In Capital, Volume III Marx used the example of the pollution of the river Thames in England. In The German Ideology (1845), Marx and Engels commented that "In the development of productive forces there comes a stage when productive forces and means of intercourse are brought into being, which, under the existing relationships, only cause mischief, and are no longer forces of production but forces of destruction (machinery and money)". [42])
  94. ^ See further, Alec Nove, The economics of feasible socialism, 2nd ed. Harper Collins, 1991; Makoto Itoh, Political Economy of Socialism. New York: St Martins Press, 1995.
  95. ^ See, for this interpretation, Maurice Dobb, Theories of value and distribution since Adam Smith. Cambridge University Press, 1973, p. 159).
  96. ^ There exists a very large international literature on the transformation problem (several thousands of articles) but since most of the authors understand little about business economics, about mathematical statistics or about Marx, and do not read German, most of it is not recommendable. The debate is usually considered to have begun in earnest with an article by Ladislaus von Bortkiewicz, "Wertrechnung und Preisrechnung im Marxschen System", in: 1907, Archiv fur Sozialwissenschaft und Sozialpolitik, XXIII-1 (1906) pp. 1-50, XXV-2 (1907) pp. 10-51, XXV-2 (1907) pp. 445-488. This article was translated into English in 1952 as "Value and Price in the Marxian System", International Economic Papers, no. 2, 1952.[43] Bortkiewicz did not actually aim to attack Marx, but solve what he perceived to be a theoretical problem in Capital, Volume III. A fairly readable exposition of the transformation problem controversy is provided e.g. in M.C. Howard & J.E. King, The political economy of Marx. Longman, 1975, chapter 5. A However, there exists no book which reviews all the transformation problem literature. A brief overview is provided online in Gérard Duménil and Duncan Foley, "The Marxian Transformation Problem." [44]
  97. ^ Participants in the "transformation problem" controversy assumed the necessity of a uniform rate of profit, while the followers of Moshe Machover and Emmanuel Farjoun (more correctly) argued that a uniform rate of profit had never existed.[45]. But no one in the debate clearly posed the question of why Marx had assumed the same rate of profit for all industries, even when he himself indicated in several places in Capital Vol. 3 that there are continuously differentials in industrial profit rates.
  98. ^ Carlo Panico, Interest and profit in the theories of value and distribution, introd. John Eatwell. London: Macmillan Press, 1988.
  99. ^ In a "globalized" world economy, this idea is of course not strictly true, since foreign investors can bet on a capital gain which they will get, if currency exchange rates change in their favour.
  100. ^ Karl Marx, Capital, Volume II. chapter 22, (emphasis added)
  101. ^ See e.g. chapter 49 in Capital Vol. 3, and Engels's letter to Conrad Schmidt dated March 12, 1895.
  102. ^ "...if the price of grain rises after a bad harvest, then its value rises, for one thing, because a given amount of labour is contained in a smaller product; for another thing, its selling price rises by much more still. What has this to do with my theory of value? The more the grain is sold over its value, the more other commodities, whether in their natural form or in money form, will be sold under their value by exactly the same amount, even if their own money price does not fall. The total value remains the same, even if the expression of this total value in its entirety were to increase in money, in other words, if the sum total of “exchange-value” according to Mr. Wagner were to rise. This is the case if we assume that the drop in price of the total of the other commodities does not cover the over-value price (excess price) of the grain. But in this case, the exchange-value of money has fallen pro tanto beneath its value; the total value of all commodities does not only remain the same, but even remains the same expressed in money, if money is included among the commodities." - Karl Marx, Notes on Adolph Wagner's “Lehrbuch der politischen Ökonomie” (Second Edition), Volume I, 1879.[46]
  103. ^ Utz-Peter Reich, National Accounts and Economic Value: A Study in Concepts (London: Palgrave/Macmillan, 2001).
  104. ^ In modern physics, the theory of time dilation implies that the passing of time is not an absolute "constant" either. In his special theory of relativity, Albert Einstein showed that observers in motion relative to one another will measure different elapsed times for the same event.
  105. ^ See: Simon Mohun and Roberto Veneziani, "The Temporal Single-System Interpretation: Underestimation and Inconsistency", Marxism 21, Vol. 6 No. 3, 2009, pp. 277-99.
  106. ^ "Surplus-value and the rate of surplus-value are.... the invisible essence to be investigated, whereas the rate of profit and hence the form of surplus-value as profit are visible surface phenomena." - Karl Marx, Capital, Volume III. Penguin, 1981, p. 134.
  107. ^ Alan Freeman "Marx without equilibrium" (July 1995)MPRA Paper No. 1207, posted November 2007.[47]
  108. ^ See further: Ian Wright, "Implicit Microfoundations for Macroeconomics". Economics: The open access, open-assessment e-journal, Vol. 3, No. 19, May 11 2009.[48]
  109. ^ "'The way you get rich in this world is not by working hard,' said Marty Sullivan [=Martin A. Sullivan], an economist and a contributing editor to Tax Analysts. 'It’s by owning large amounts of assets and having those things appreciate in value.'" - Steven Mufson and Jia Lynn Yang, "Capital gains tax rates benefiting wealthy feed growing gap between rich and poor", in: Washington Post, 12 September 2011.
  110. ^ "Our concern is... to discover and present the conrcete forms which grow out of the process of capital's movement considered as a whole... The configurations of capital, as developed in this volume, thus approach step by step the form in which they appear on the surface of society, in the action of different capitals on one another, i.e. in competition, and in the everyday consciousness of the agents of production themselves." - Karl Marx, Capital, Volume III, Penguin ed., chapter 1, p. 117.
  111. ^ See e.g. Willi Semmler, Competition, Monopoly, and Differential Profit Rates; On the Relevance of the Classical and Marxian Theories of Production Prices for Modern Industrial and Corporate Pricing. Columbia University Press, 1984.
  112. ^ Interview with Andrew Glyn by Rob Hoveman, Socialist Review, July 2006.[49]
  113. ^ A pioneering work aiming to reaggregate official statistics in line with Marxian categories was: Shane Mage, "The Law of the Falling Tendency of the Rate of Profit; Its Place in the Marxian Theoretical System and Relevance to the US Economy". Phd Thesis, Columbia University, 1963 (available from Scribd). See further: Anwar Shaikh, The Empirical Strength of the Labor Theory of Value. In: Riccardo Bellofiore (ed.), Conference Proceedings of Marxian Economics: A Centenary Appraisal. London: Macmillan, 1998 [50]; a classic study is Anwar Shaikh & Ergutul Tonak, Measuring the Wealth of Nations: The Political Economy of National Accounts. Cambridge University Press, 1994. Particularly from the 1980s onwards, there were many more attempts to test Marx's value theory against empirical data. The results are reported in journals such as Science & Society,Research in Political Economy, Review of Radical Political Economics, Cambridge Journal of Economics, Review of the Fernand Braudel Centre, Capital & Class etc.
  114. ^ See e.g. Anwar Shaikh, "Neo-Ricardian economics: a wealth of algebra, a poverty of theory". In: Review of radical political economics, Vol. 14 no. 2, 1982.[51] Shaikh and his students subsequently developed a number of empirical tests of Marx's theory of value.
  115. ^ "It lies outside the scope of our plan to give a detailed analysis of the credit system and the instruments this creates (credit money, etc.). Only a few points will be emphasized here, which are necessary to characterize the capitalist mode of production in general. In this connection, we shall simply be dealing with commercial and bank credit. The connection between the development of this and the development of state credit remains outside our discussion." - Karl Marx, Capital, Volume III, Penguin ed., p. 525.
  116. ^ John Authers, "Why 'efficient markets' collapse", video interview with Benoit Mandelbrot, in: Financial Times website, 30 September 2009. Mandelbrot argued deftly that the simplicity of prices is that they can "only go up or down".[52] But this sidesteps the whole problem that many different prices can be calculated for the same good, for all kinds of different purposes, using different valuation assumptions. Thus, for example, the financial crisis of 2007-2010 was widely blamed on "wrong risk-pricing", wrong in the sense that the risks had been wrongly valued. Suppose that a vulgar economist and a sophisticated economist discuss selling an apple worth 25 cents. The sophisticated economist suggests cutting the apple into six slices and selling them for 5 cents each. Mandelbrot would then say the price of the apple has risen from 25 cents to 30 cents, but in fact the apple has been repackaged into a new product, namely apple slices with new terms of trade. In economics this is called product differentiation. This is just a simple example, but assets can be combined and repackaged in numerous different ways, in which case the price does not simply go up or down but refers to a different kind of deal. The same product can be traded on different terms.
  117. ^ "The price-form... is not only compatible with the possibility of a quantitative incongruity between magnitude of value and price, i.e., between the former and its expression in money, but it may also conceal a qualitative inconsistency, so much so, that, although money is nothing but the value-form of commodities, price ceases altogether to express value." - Marx, Capital Vol. 1, ch 3, section 1 [53]
  118. ^ "...if one wanted to 'explain' from the outset all phenomena that apparently contradict the law, one would have to provide the science before the science. (...) The vulgar economist has not the slightest idea that the actual, everyday exchange relations and the value magnitudes cannot be directly identical. (...) The vulgar economist thinks he has made a great discovery when, faced with the disclosure of the intrinsic interconnection, he insists that things look different in appearance. In fact, he prides himself in his clinging to appearances and believing them to be the ultimate. Why then have science at all?" - Letter of Karl Marx to Ludwig Kugelmann, London, 11 July 1868 (MECW, Volume 43, p. 67).[54]
  119. ^ Out of the four volumes of Das Kapital, Marx published only the first one. His manuscripts for the second and third volume were edited together by Friedrich Engels, and a fourth volume was edited together by Karl Kautsky as Theories of Surplus Value. On the conditions under which Marx wrote his texts, see e.g. Francis Wheen, Karl Marx: a life. W. W. Norton & Company, 2001.
  120. ^ Steve Keen, Debunking Economics; The Naked Emperor of the Social Sciences. London: Zed Press, 2005. [55] and [56]. A second edition was recently published
  121. ^ Ernest Mandel, Late Capitalism. London: NLB, 1975, p. 94.